Capital Regulation and Tail Risk
  • 1 0000000404811396https://isni.org/isni/0000000404811396International Monetary Fund
  • | 2 0000000404811396https://isni.org/isni/0000000404811396International Monetary Fund

Contributor Notes

The paper studies risk mitigation associated with capital regulation, in a context where banks may choose tail risk asserts. We show that this undermines the traditional result that high capital reduces excess risk-taking driven by limited liability. Moreover, higher capital may have an unintended effect of enabling banks to take more tail risk without the fear of breaching the minimal capital ratio in non-tail risky project realizations. The results are consistent with stylized facts about pre-crisis bank behavior, and suggest implications for the optimal design of capital regulation.

Abstract

The paper studies risk mitigation associated with capital regulation, in a context where banks may choose tail risk asserts. We show that this undermines the traditional result that high capital reduces excess risk-taking driven by limited liability. Moreover, higher capital may have an unintended effect of enabling banks to take more tail risk without the fear of breaching the minimal capital ratio in non-tail risky project realizations. The results are consistent with stylized facts about pre-crisis bank behavior, and suggest implications for the optimal design of capital regulation.

I. Introduction

Regulatory reform in the wake of the recent financial crisis has focused on an increase in capital cushions of financial intermediaries. Basel III rules have doubled the minimal capital ratio, and directed banks to hold excess capital as conservation and countercyclical buffers above the minimum (BIS, 2010). These arrangements complement traditional moral suasion and individual targets used by regulators to ensure adequate capital cushions.

There are two key arguments in favor of higher capital. The first is an ex post argument: capital can be seen as a buffer that absorbs losses and hence reduces the risk of insolvency. This risk absorption role also mitigates systemic risk factors, such as collective uncertainty over counterparty risk, which had a devastating propagation effect during the recent crisis. The second considers the ex ante effects of buffers: capital reduces limited liability-driven incentives of bank shareholders to take excessive risk, by increasing their “skin in the game” (potential loss in case of bank failure; Jensen and Meckling 1976, Holmstrom and Tirole 1997).

Yet some recent experience calls for caution. First, banks are increasingly exposed to tail risk, which causes losses only rarely, but when those materialize they often exceed any plausible initial capital. Such risks can result from a number of strategies. A first example are carry trades reliant on short term wholesale funding, which in 2007-2008 produced highly correlated distressed sales (Gorton, 2010). A second example is the reckless underwriting of contingent liabilities on systemic risk, callable at times of collective distress (Acharya and Richardson, 2009). Finally, the combination of higher profits in normal times and massive losses occasionally arises in undiversified industry exposures to inflated housing markets (Shin, 2009). A useful review of such strategies is provided in Acharya et al. (2009); IMF (2010) highlights the importance of recognizing tail risk in financial stability analysis. Since under tail risk banks do not internalize losses independently of the level of initial capital, the buffer and incentive effects of capital diminish. Higher capital may become a less effective way of controlling bank risk.

Second, a number of major banks, particularly in the United States, appeared highly capitalized just a couple of years prior to the crisis. Yet these very intermediaries took excessive risks (often tail risk, or highly negatively skewed gambles). In fact, anecdotal evidence suggests that highly capitalized banks were looking for ways to put at risk their capital in order to produce returns for shareholders (Berger et al. 2008, Huang and Ratnovski 2009). Therefore, higher capital may create incentives for risk-taking instead of mitigating them.

This paper seeks to study these concerns by reviewing the effectiveness of capital regulation, and in particular of excess capital buffers (that is, above minimum ratios), in dealing with tail risk events. We reach two key results.

First, we show that the traditional buffer and incentives effects of capital become less powerful when banks have access to tail risk projects. The reason is that tail risk realizations can wipe out almost any level of capital. Left tails limit the effectiveness of capital as the absorbing buffer and restrict “skin in the game” because a part of the losses is never borne by shareholders.

Hence, under tail risk, excess risk-shifting incentives of bank shareholders may exist almost independently of the level of initial or required capital.

Second, having established that under tail risk the benefits of higher capital are limited, we consider its possible unintended effects. We note that capital regulation also affects bank risk choices through the threat of capital adjustment costs when banks have to raise equity to comply with minimum capital ratios. (These costs are most commonly associated with equity dilution under asymmetric information on the value of illiquid bank assets, Myers and Majluf, 1984, or reduced managerial incentives for efficiency, Jensen, 1986).2 Similar to “skin in the game”, capital adjustment costs make banks averse to risk, and may discourage risky bank strategies. However, unlike “skin in the game”, the incentive effects of capital adjustment costs fall with higher bank capital because the probability of breaching the minimal capital ratio decreases.

Of course, if highly capitalized banks internalized all losses, they would have taken risk only if that was socially optimal (would have offered a higher NPV). Yet this result changes dramatically once we introduce tail risk. Then, even banks with high capital never internalize all losses, and may take excess risk. Moreover, the relationship between capital and risk can become non-monotonic. The reason is interesting. In the first place, tail risk leads to insolvency whatever the initial bank capital, so higher capital does not sufficiently discourage risk-taking for well capitalized banks through “skin in the game”. At the same time, higher excess capital allows banks to take the riskier projects without breaching the minimal capital ratio (and incurring large capital adjustment costs) in the case of low (non tail) returns. So under tail risk, higher capital may create conditions where highly capitalized banks take more excess risk. Further, we show that the negative effect of extra capital on risk-taking becomes stronger when banks get access to projects with even higher tail risk.

To close the model, we derive the bank’s choice of initial capital in the presence of tail risk, and the implications for optimal capital regulation. We show that a bank may choose to hold higher capital in order to create a cushion over the minimal capital requirement so as to be able to take tail risk without the fear of a corrective action in case of marginally negative project realizations. Then, capital regulation has to implement two bounds on the values of bank capital: a bound from below (a minimal capital ratio) to prevent ordinary risk-shifting and a bound from above (realistically, in the form of special attention devoted to banks with particularly high capital) in order to assure that they are not taking tail risk.

These results are interesting to consider in historic context. Most sources of tail risk that we described are related to recent financial innovations. In the past, tail risk in traditional loan-oriented depository banking was low (both project returns and withdrawals largely satisfied the law of large numbers), hence “skin in the game” effects dominated, and extra capital led to lower risk-taking. Yet now, when banks have access to tail risk projects, the buffer and “skin in the game” effects that are the cornerstone of the traditional approach to capital regulation became weak, while effects where higher capital enables risk-taking became stronger. Therefore, due to financial innovation, the beneficial effects of higher capital were reduced, while the scope for undesirable effects increased.

The paper has policy implications relevant for the current debate on strengthening capital regulation. The simpler conclusion is that it is impossible to control all aspects of risk-taking using a single instrument. The problem of capital buffers is that they are effective as long as they can minimize not just the chance of default, but also the loss given default. Contractual innovation in finance has enabled intermediaries to manufacture risk profiles which allow them to take maximum advantage of limited liability even with high levels of capital. The key to contain gambles with skewed returns is to either prohibit extreme bets, or to increase their ex ante cost. Leading policy proposals now emerging are to charge prudential levies on strategies exposed to systemic risk (Acharya et al., 2010), such as extremely mismatched strategies (Perotti and Suarez, 2009, 2010), or derivative positions written on highly correlated risks.

A more intricate conclusion relates to implications for capital regulation. The results do not imply that less capital is better: this was not the case in recent years. However, they suggest the following. First, regulators should acknowledge that traditional capital regulation has limitations in dealing with tail risk. This is similar, for example, to an already-accepted understanding that it has limitations in dealing with correlation risk (Acharya, 2009). Second, banks with significant excess capital may be induced to take excess risk (in order to use or put at risk their capital), as amply demonstrated by the crisis experience. Hence, simply relying on higher and “excess” capital of banks as a means of crisis prevention may have ruinous effects if it produces a false sense of comfort. Finally, authorities should introduce complementary measures to target tail risk next to the policy on pro-cyclical and conservation buffers. In this context, enhanced supervision with a focus on capturing tail risk may be essential.

We see our paper as related to two key strands of the banking literature. First are the papers on the unintended effects of bank capital regulation. Early papers (Kahane 1977, Kim and Santomero 1988, Koehn and Santomero 1980) took a portfolio optimization approach to banking and caution that higher capital requirements can lead to an increase in risk of the risky part of the bank’s portfolio. Later studies focus on incentive effects. Boot and Greenbaum (1993) show that capital requirements can negatively affect asset quality due to a reduction in monitoring incentives. Blum (1999), Caminal and Matutes (2002), Flannery (1989) and Hellman et al. (2000) argue that higher capital can make banks take more risk as they attempt to compensate for the cost of capital. Our paper follows this literature, with a distinct and contemporary focus on tail risk.3 On the empirical front, Angora et al. (2009) and Bichsel and Blum (2004) find a positive correlation between levels of capital and bank risk-taking.

The second strand are the recent papers on the regulatory implications of increased sophistication of financial intermediaries and the recent crisis. These papers generally argue that dealing with new risks (including systemic and tail risk) requires new regulatory tools (Acharya and Yorulmazer 2007, Acharya et al. 2010, Brunnermeier and Pedersen 2008, Huang and Ratnovski 2011, Perotti and Suarez 2009, 2010).

The structure of the paper is as follows. Section 2 outlines the theoretical model. Section 3 describes the traditional “skin in the game” effect of capital on risk-taking. Section 4 shows how higher capital can enable risk-taking when banks have access to tail risk projects. Section 5 endogenizes bank’s choice of initial capital and provides insights for optimal capital regulation. Section 6 concludes. The proofs and extensions are in the Appendix.

II. The Model

The model has three main ingredients. First, the bank is managed by an owner-manager (hereafter, the banker) with limited liability, who can opportunistically engage in asset substitution. Second, the bank operates in a prudential framework based on a minimal capital ratio, with a capital adjustment cost if the bank fails to meet the ratio and has to raise extra equity. Finally, the bank has access to tail risk projects. Such a setup is a stylized representation of the key relevant features of the modern banking system. There are three dates (0,12,1), no discounting, and everyone is risk-neutral.

The bank At date 0, the bank has capital C and deposits D. For convenience, we normalize C + D = 1. Deposits are fully insured at no cost to the bank; they carry a 0 interest rate and need to be repaid at date 1.4

The bank has access to two alternative investment projects. Both require an outlay of 1 at date 0 (all resources available to the bank), and produce return at date 1. The return of the safe project is certain: Rs > 1. The return of the risky project is probabilistic: high, RH > RS, with probability p; low, 0 < RL < 1, with probability 1 − p − µ; or extremely low, R0 = 0, with probability µ. We consider the risky project with three outcomes in order to capture both the second (variance) and the third (skewness, or “left tail”, driven by the R0 realization) moments of the project’s payoff.

In the spirit of the asset substitution literature, we assume that the net present value (NPV) of the safe project is higher than that of the risky project:

RS>pRH+(1pμ)RL,(1)

and yet the return on the safe asset, RS, is not too high, so that the banker has incentives to choose the risky project at least for low levels of initial capital:

RS1<p(RH1).(2)

The left-hand side of (2) is the banker’s expected payoff from investing in the safe project, and the right-hand side is the expected payoff from shifting to the risky project, conditional on bank having no initial capital, C = 0 and D = 1. We consequently study conditions under which the bank’s leverage creates incentives to opportunistically choose the suboptimal, risky project.

For definiteness, the bank chooses the safe project when indifferent. The bank has no continuation value beyond date 1. (We discuss the impact of a positive continuation value in the Appendix; it reduces bank risk-taking but does not affect our qualitative results.)

The bank’s project choice is unobservable and unverifiable. However, the return of the project chosen by the bank becomes observable and verifiable before final returns are realized, at date 12.5 This allows the regulator to impose corrective action on an undercapitalized bank.

Capital regulation Capital regulation is based on the minimal capital (leverage) ratio. We take this regulatory design as exogenous, since it is the key feature of Basel regulation. We define the bank’s capital ratio, c = (A − D)/A, where A is the value of bank assets, D is the face value of deposits, and A−D is its economic capital. At date 0, before the investment is undertaken, the capital ratio is c = C/(C + D) = C. At dates 12 and 1 the capital ratio is ci = (RiD)/Ri, with i ∈ {S, H, L, 0} reflecting project choice and realization. The fact that the date 12 capital position is defined in a forward-looking way is consistent with the practice of banks recognizing known future gains or losses.

At any point in time, the bank’s capital ratio c must exceed a minimum cmin, cmin > 0. We assume that the minimal ratio is satisfied at date 0: c > cmin. Consequently, the minimal ratio is also satisfied for realizations RS (when the bank chooses the safe project) and RH (when the bank chooses the risky project and is successful): cH > cS > c > cmin, since RH > RS > 1. The minimal capital ratio is never satisfied for R0 (in the extreme low outcome of the risky project), since the bank’s capital is negative, c0 = −∞ < 0 < cmin. In a low realization of the risky project RL the banks’ capital sufficiency is ambiguous. As we will show below, depending on the bank’s initial capital, it can be positive and sufficient, cL > cmin, or positive but insufficient, 0 < cL < cmin, or negative, cL < 0.

The regulator imposes corrective action at date 12 if a bank fails to satisfy the minimal capital ratio. The banker is given two options. One is to surrender the bank to the regulator. Then, the bank’s equity value is wiped out and the banker receives a zero payoff. Alternatively, the bank can attract additional capital to bring its capital ratio to the regulatory minimum, cmin. We assume that attracting capital carries a cost for the existing bank shareholder. The cost reflects the dilution when equity issues are viewed by new investors as negative signals, or when there is a downward sloping demand for bank’s shares. Both factors may be especially strong when the offering is performed with urgency. The presence of such costs is well established in the literature (Asquith and Mullins, 1986). In the main model, we treat the cost of recapitalization as fixed at T. In the Appendix we discuss a specification with concave cost (i.e., the cost of recapitalization falls with higher bank capital) and show that it does not affect our results. The banker chooses to abandon rather than recapitalize the bank when indifferent.

Timeline The model outcomes and the sequence of events are depicted in Figure 1.

Figure 1.
Figure 1.

The timeline

Citation: IMF Working Papers 2011, 188; 10.5089/9781462308262.001.A001

Intuition Figure 2 provides a simple, illustrative intuition for the effects that we intend to capture in our formal analysis. Consider a bank that chooses between a safe and a risky project, and note how the bank’s level of initial capital affects that choice. The classic Myers and Majluf (1984) channel focuses on the consequences of limited liability, which subsidizes risk-taking and tilts the bank’s incentives towards a risky project. Then, higher capital discourages risk-taking by making shareholders internalize more of the bank’s losses in the bad outcome (“skin in the game”, the left panel). We introduce an additional effect associated with the minimal capital requirements. A bank with positive but insufficient capital is subject to costly corrective action: shareholders have to recapitalize or abandon the bank. This penalizes risky projects. Then, a bank with higher capital may choose more risk, because higher capital reduces the probability of breaching the minimal capital ratio (the capital adjustment cost effect, the center panel). Of course, if a highly capitalized bank internalized all the costs of risk-taking, it would choose the risky project only if that was socially optimal (offered a higher NPV). To formalize the excess risk-taking of highly capitalized banks, we combine the two effects in a framework where a bank’s risky project can both marginally breach the minimal capital ratio (triggering a capital adjustment cost) and result in an extremely negative outcome (tail risk, which falls under the limited liability constraint, the right panel). We find that, as a result of the combination of the two effects, the relationship between bank capital and risk-taking may become non-linear. In particular – the key result that we will emphasize – banks with higher capital may choose inefficiently high risk, when such risk has a significant tail component.

Figure 2.
Figure 2.

The two opposite effects of capital on bank risk-taking

Citation: IMF Working Papers 2011, 188; 10.5089/9781462308262.001.A001

The return function with three outcomes is the simplest form that supports the insights of this model. The distinction between the marginal bad (low) and the extreme bad (tail) realization is necessary to simultaneously capture the effects of aversion to recapitalization and risk-shifting. Our results can also arise in more general distributions, including continuous, risky return distributions having similar features: a mass in the left tail and a possibility of marginally negative outcomes.

III. “Skin in the gameand tail risk

In this section we show that the traditional “skin in the game” incentive effects of higher capital on risk-taking become weaker when the bank has access to tail risk projects. This brings us to the first policy result, that capital regulation may have limited effectiveness in dealing with tail risk.

Throughout the section, we abstract from the effects of capital adjustment costs (we assume no minimum capital ratio), which we introduce in the next section. We solve the model backwards: first deriving the payoffs depending on bank project choice, and then the project choice itself. The solution is followed by comparative statics and a calibration exercise.

A. Payoff and project choice

Consider the bank with access to a tail risk project (µ ≥ 0), in a setup with no capital adjustment costs (T = 0). The banker’s payoff from choosing the safe project is:

ST=0=RSD=RS(1c).(3)

The banker’s payoff from choosing the risky project is:

RT=0=p.[RH(1c)]+(1pμ)max{RL(1c);0},(4)

where on the right hand side of (4) the first term is the expected payoff in RH realization, and the second term is the expected payoff in RL realization. The third realization, R0, occurs with probability µ and carries a zero payoff.

The bank chooses the safe project over the risky project when:

ST=0RT=0,

which is equivalent to:

RS(1c)p[RH(1c)]+(1pμ)max{[RL(1c)];0}.(5)

The following Proposition describes the bank’s investment decision.

The bank’s project choice depends on its initial capital c:

(a) For
RS<pRH+(1p)RL,(6)
the bank chooses the safe project if
c1RSpRH(1pμ)RLμ
and the risky project otherwise;
(b) For
RSpRH+(1p)RL,(7)
the bank chooses the safe project if
c1RSpRH1p
and the risky project otherwise.

See Appendix.■

The intuition for Case (b) of the above proposition is that when RS is high enough, the bank’s risk-shifting incentives are so low that the bank will only take a risky project when it has negative capital under the RL realization, allowing it to shift more of the downside to the creditors. Then, the bank gets the same zero payoff in the R0 and RL realizations and its project choice is not affected by the tail risk probability µ. Case (b) therefore represents the case of negligible tail risk. We therefore further focus on Case (a), which allows us to study the impact of tail risk on bank’s project choice. We denote:

cT=0=1RSpRH(1pμ)RLμ,(8)

with cT=0 being the threshold for risk-shifting incentives under (6).

B. Comparative statics

We study how the threshold cT=0, the initial capital necessary to prevent the bank from risk-shifting, is affected by the project’s tail risk µ. To maintain comparability, we consider transformations of the risky project that increase µ but preserve its expected value, denoted by E(R). There are various ways to alter model parameters to achieve that, but we highlight the two with the best interpretations, which we analyze in turn.

Some of the sources of tail risk in the recent crisis were carry trades or undiversified exposures to housing markets. Such activities transform the distribution of the risky project towards extreme outcomes: within the confines of our models we can interpret that as a shift in the probability mass from RL to R0 and RH. Formally, that implies an increase in µ and p, at the expense of (1 − pµ). To keep E(R) constant, following to an increase in µ by ∆µ, p should increase by RLRHRLΔμ.

Using (8), we find that:
cT=0μ|E(R)=constant=RSE(R)μ2>0.(9)

So that the amount of capital necessary to prevent risk-shifting increases in tail risk.

Another source of tail risk was the underwriting of contingent liabilities on market risk; in this case the bank obtains ex-ante premia (higher return) in all cases when the tail risk is not realized. Formally, this can be interpreted as a higher µ compensated by higher RL and RH, so that E(R) is constant. In order to achieve this, following an increase in µ by ∆µ, both RL and RH should increase by RLΔμ1μΔμ.

Similarly to the previous case, using (8), we find that:
cT=0μ|E(R)=constant=RSE(R)μ2>0.

Hence, again, the amount of capital necessary to prevent risk-shifting increases in tail risk.

In both cases, observe that cT=0 grows logarithmically in µ.6 Therefore, capital becomes progressively a less effective incentive tool for controlling bank risk-taking as tail risk µ increases, with the effect most pronounced for low values of µ. As an implication, tail risk limits the effectiveness of capital regulation in dealing with bank risk-taking incentives.

C. Economic significance: a quantitative example

The comparative statics exercise verified that, as banks are able to take projects with higher tail risk µ, the buffer and incentive effects of capital diminish. Thus, in order to prevent banks from taking tail risk projects using minimal capital-based (“skin in the game”) incentives only, banks will need progressively higher levels of initial capital cT=0. This section attempts to highlight the economic significance of these results through a simple calibration exercise.

Consider the following calibration parameters: RS = 1.03, RH = 1.14, RL = 0.92, p = 50%, and µ = 1%. Then, the expected return on the safe project is 3%, the expected return on the risky project is 2.1%, and the minimal level of capital necessary to prevent risk-shifting is cT=0 = 8%. We take these parameter values as representing the case of low (or usual) tail risk.

We ask how cT=0 changes if tail risk µ increases, holding the expected value of the risky project fixed, as in the comparative statics exercise, by adjusting p to compensate for higher µ (Case 1 in Section 3.2). The result of the calibration exercise is shown on Figure 3. As µ increases, so does cT=0, and the increase in cT=0 is economically significant. Indeed, even an increase in µ from 1% to 1.1% increases the initial capital necessary to prevent risk-shifting from 8% to 16.4%. A doubling of µ to 2% percent increases the necessary initial capital to as much as 54%. Such values of initial capital are likely implausible in practice.

Figure 3.
Figure 3.

Tail risk and the initial capital required to prevent risk-shifting

Citation: IMF Working Papers 2011, 188; 10.5089/9781462308262.001.A001

The calibration confirmed that at least under some plausible circumstances, minimal capital requirements alone cannot prevent banks from taking excess tail risk, because the level of capital necessary for that would need to be implausibly high. In the next section, we study how the costly corrective action on undercapitalized banks may complement the capital requirements in dealing with bank risk-taking.

IV. Tail risk and the unintended effects of higher capital

In the previous section, we showed that capital becomes a less effective tool for controlling bank risk-taking in the presence of tail risk. We will now introduce an additional feature – capital adjustment costs – to obtain a stronger result. In addition to being a less powerful tool, higher capital may have unintended effects of enabling banks’ risk-taking. Specifically, we show that marginally capitalized banks do not take risk because they are averse to breaching the minimal capital ratio in mildly negative realizations of the risky project (RL). Yet banks with higher capital can take more risk because their chance of breaching the ratio in such realizations is lower. Further, in comparative statics, we demonstrate that the unintended effects of higher capital are stronger when banks get access to projects with higher tail risk.

As before, we solve the model backwards: first we derive the payoffs depending on bank project choice, then the project choice itself. The solution is followed by comparative statics.

A. Payoffs and the recapitalization decision

The banker’s payoff from choosing the safe project is:

S=RSD=RS(1c).

Now consider the banker’s payoff from the risky project. When the project returns RH, the banker obtains RH − (1 − c). When the project returns R0, the banker obtains zero.

The case when the risky project returns RL is more complex, because depending on the relative values of c and RL, the bank’s capital may be positive and sufficient, positive but insufficient, or negative. Consider these in turn.

Under RL, the bank has positive and sufficient capital (cL ≥ cmin) when:

RL(1c)RLcmin,

which gives:

ccSufficient=1(1cmin)RL.(10)

Then, the bank continues to date 1, repays depositors, and obtains RL − (1 − c).

When c < cSufficient, RL leaves the bank with insufficient capital, cL < cmin, so it has to be abandoned or recapitalized at cost T. The banker chooses to recapitalize the bank for:

RL(1c)T>0,(11)

where the left-hand side is the banker’s return after repaying depositors net off the recapitalization cost, and the right hand side is the zero return in case the bank is abandoned. Expression (11) can be re-written as:

c>cRecapitalize=1+TRL.(12)

We focus our analysis on the case when cRecapitalize < cSufficient, corresponding to:

T<cminRL,(13)

so that there exist values of c: cRecapitalize < c < cSufficient, where the banker chooses to recapitalize the bank in the RL realization, instead of abandoning it. When T is larger than cmin RL, the banker always abandons a bank with insufficient capital. Note that both thresholds cRecapitalize and cSufficient are in the (0, 1) interval.

Figure 4 illustrates the bank’s recapitalization decision.

Figure 4.
Figure 4.

Bank’s recapitalization decision and payoffs

The bank’s recapitalization decision and banker’s payoffs as a function of initial capital c, upon the realization of low return RL are as follows. For ccSufficient, the bank has positive and sufficient capital at date ½. The bank continues to date 1, repays depositors and obtains a positive payoff. For c < cSufficient, the bank has positive and insufficient or negative capital. The bank can be either abandoned or recapitalized. The bank is abandoned for ccRecapitalize. As a result the bank is closed and the banker gets a zero payoff. The bank is recapitalized at a cost for cRecapitalize < c <cSufficient. The bank continues to date 1, repays depositors, pays the recapitalization cost, and obtains a positive payoff.

Citation: IMF Working Papers 2011, 188; 10.5089/9781462308262.001.A001

Overall, the banker’s payoff in the RL realization of the risky project is:

L={RL(1c), if ccsufficientRL(1c)T, if cRecapitalize<c<cSufficient,0, if ccRecapitalize(14)

and the overall payoff to the risky project is:

R=p[RH(1c)]+(1pμ)L.(15)

B. Project choice

We now consider the bank’s project choice at date 0, depending on its initial capital c. The bank chooses the safe project over the risky one for:

SR,

which is equivalent to:

RS(1c)p[RH(1c)]+(1pμ)L.(16)

To describe the results we introduce two thresholds:

W=pRH+(1p)RLμcminRL,(17)

and

Z=pRH+(1p)(RLT)+μ(TcminRL).(18)

W is a threshold point for the presence of risk-shifting in bank with high capital. For RS < W there exist values of initial capital such that even a well-capitalized bank with ccSufficient may still engage in risk-shifting. Z is a threshold point for the presence of the capital adjustment cost effect. For RSZ there exist values of initial capital such that a less capitalized bank (cRecapitalize < c < cSufficient) may choose a safe project to prevent recapitalization costs upon the RL realization of the risky project. The derivation of the thresholds is in the Appendix; the Appendix also verifies that Z < W.

Then, the risk-shifting and capital adjustment effect of bank project choice interact with each other as follows:

The bank’s project choice is characterized by thresholds c* and c**:

(a) For Z ≤ RS < W, there exist c* < cSufficient, and c** > cSufficient, such that

  • For c < c* the bank chooses the risky project and may abandon or recapitalize it upon the RL realization;

  • For c*c < cSufficient the bank chooses the safe project to avoid abandonment or recapitalization upon the RL realization; the choice of the safe project here represents the capital adjustment cost effect;

  • For cSufficientc < c** the bank chooses the risky project because its capital is high enough to avoid breaching the minimal capital ratio in the RL realization; the choice of the risky project here represents risk-shifting enabled by higher capital;

  • For cc** the bank chooses the safe project because its capital is high enough to prevent risk-shifting;

(b) For RS < Z, there exists c** > cSufficient such that for c < c** the bank chooses the risky project and for c ≥ c** the safe project; there is only a risk-shifting effect: a bank with c < cSufficient never chooses a safe project to avoid recapitalization cost;

(c) for RS ≥ W, there exists c* < cSufficient such that for initial capital c < c* the bank chooses a risky project, and for c ≥ c* the safe project; there is only a capital adjustment cost effect: a bank with c > cSufficient never engages in risk-shifting.

See Appendix.■

The thresholds:

c*=1RSpRH(1pμ)(RLT)μ,(19)

and:

c**=1RSpRH(1pμ)RLμ,(20)

are also derived in Appendix.

Case (a) of Proposition 2 contains the main result of our paper: that the relationship between bank capital and risk-taking can be non-monotonic in the presence of tail risk and capital adjustment cost. When capital is very low, c<c*, the banker faces strong risk-shifting incentives and a low cost of abandoning the bank, hence chooses high risk. For intermediate initial capital, c*c < cSufficient, the banker’s equity value is higher, and the banker chooses a safe project to avoid abandoning or recapitalizing the bank in the RL realization. The choice of the safe project is driven by capital adjustment cost -a novel effect highlighted in this paper. Yet as soon as the bank has initial capital high enough to satisfy the minimal ratio in the RL realization, for cSufficientc < c**, the capital adjustment cost stops being binding and the banker again switches to the risky project, driven by the risk-shifting effect. Finally, for very high levels of capital, c ≥ c**, the banker has so much skin in the game that risk-shifting incentives are not binding. This is the traditional effect of capital regulation; recall that under tail risk c** may be prohibitively very high. The bank’s project choice is depicted in Figure 5.

Figure 5.
Figure 5.

Bank’s project choice

The bank’s project choice depending on the level of initial capital, in Case (a) of Proposition 2: The relationship between bank capital and risk-taking is non-linear and is characterized by two thresholds as follows. When the level of capital is low (c<c*), the bank prefers the risky project, while for high level of capital (cc**) the safe project is chosen. For intermediate level of capital (c* ≤<c**), the bank prefers either the safe project (for c*c<cSufficient) or the risky one (for cSufficien tc <c**).

Citation: IMF Working Papers 2011, 188; 10.5089/9781462308262.001.A001

C. Comparative statics

In this section we repeat the comparative statics exercise of Section 3.2, in the presence of capital adjustment costs – with respect to the Case (a) of Proposition 2. We show that when tail risk increases (the risky project has a heavier left tail), highly capitalized banks get stronger incentives to take excess risk. We use the two transformations of the risky project highlighted in Section 3.2.

When a higher µ is compensated by a higher p, keeping E(R) constant, that affects both thresholds c*and c**. To focus on banker’s incentives to take excessive risk, we consider the interval [cSufficient, c**), corresponding to levels of initial bank capital for which the bank undertakes the risky project. Note that cSufficient is determined only by cmin and RL (see (10)), and hence is unaffected by a change in the probability distribution of the risky project. The critical threshold for the discussion is therefore c**. From (8), c** = cT=0. The impact of the change in probability distribution of the risky project on c** is the same as in (9):
c**μ|E(R)=constant=RSE(R)μ2>0.

This means that when tail risk increases, the interval [cSufficient, c**) on which a well-capitalized bank chooses the risky project expands. Interestingly, the interval expands because banks with higher capital start taking more risk. This highlights the relationship between tail risk and the unintended effects of higher bank capital. The intuition is that when investment returns become more polarized, they enable well-capitalized banks to earn higher profits in good time, while at the same time reducing the expected cost of recapitalization since the intermediate low return RL is less frequent. Unintended effects of bank capital affect specifically the well-capitalized banks. Figure 6a illustrates the case.

Figure 6a.
Figure 6a.

Bank’s project choice when the risky project has a heavier left tail. Case 1

A heavier left tail is characterized by a higher probability for the extremely low outcome (i.e., a higher µ). A change in the return profile of the risky project following a change in probability distribution (i.e., both p and µ are increased, other else equal, such that the expected value of the risky project remains the same), affects both thresholds c* and c* and c**. The interval [ cSufficient, c**) widens, suggesting that well-capitalized banks which behave prudently in absence of tail risk projects, have a strong incentive to undertake more risk, if projects with heavier left tail are available in economy.

Citation: IMF Working Papers 2011, 188; 10.5089/9781462308262.001.A001

When a higher µ is compensated by higher RL and RH, this change in the return profile of the risky asset affects thresholds c*, c**, and cSufficient. To focus on the incentives of well-capitalized banks to take excessive risk, we again consider the interval [cSufficient, c**). Note that cSufficient is decreasing in RL (see (10)) and hence in µ. At the same time, from (9), c** is increasing in µ. Hence here the interval [cSufficient.c**) widens even more in µ than in case 1, and both more and less capitalized banks start choosing the risky projects. Figure 6b illustrates the case.

Figure 6b.
Figure 6b.

Bank’s project choice when the risky project has a heavier left tail. Case 2

A heavier left tail is characterized by a higher probability for the extremely low outcome (i.e., a higher µ). A change in the return profile of the risky project following a change in probability distribution (i.e., µ is increased), compensated by higher RL and RH, other else equal, such that the expected value of the risky project remains the same, affects thresholds c* and c**, and cSufficient as well. The interval [cSufficient, c**) widens even more, suggesting that both well and less capitalized banks will start choosing the risky project.

Citation: IMF Working Papers 2011, 188; 10.5089/9781462308262.001.A001

V. Bank capital choices and optimal capital regulation

We have previously identified how bank incentives to take tail risk depend on its initial level of capital. We can now study how the ability of banks to take tail risk affects bank capital choices and what are the implications for the optimal capital regulation. To endogenize bank capital choice, we need to introduce the bank’s cost of holding capital. We assume that:

(A) The bank’s private cost of holding capital is cγ, γ>1. This cost represents the alternative cost of using banker’s own funds elsewhere, see Hellmann et al. (2000). The assumption assures that, all else equal, the bank will want to hold as little capital as possible.

(B) The cost of bank capital becomes prohibitive for high values of capital, making cmin=c* impossible to implement. Recall that, under tail risk, c** (the level of capital necessary to prevent bank risk-taking solely through the “skin-in-the-game” channel) can become very high (Section 3.3).

We can now formulate the result on the bank’s endogenous choice of initial capital. We focus on case Case (a) of Proposition 2 where the relationship between bank capital and risk-taking is non-monotonic in bank capital.

Setting cmin < c* is never optimal (because the bank will always choose cmin and a risky project); therefore cmin ≥ c*.

It follows from Proposition 2 and Assumption A.■

We can now formulate the result on the bank’s capital choice:

For cmin ≥ c*, the bank’s private capital choice is either the minimal capital cmin or the level of capital sufficient to avoid recapitalization costs in the RL realization of the risky project cSufficient. There exists γ* > 1:
γ*=1+μRL1RLRSpRH(1pμ)RL(1cmin)(1RL)(21)
such that the bank chooses cSufficient for γ < γ* and cmin otherwise.

See Appendix.■

The intuition is as follows. Because capital is costly, the bank will choose the lowest capital possible on each of the intervals [cmin, cSufficient) and [cSufficient, c**). Capital below cmin is ruled out by capital regulation under Lemma 1 and capital at or above c** is ruled out by assumption B above. To establish the bank’s choice for capital we therefore have to compare profits at two points: cmin and cSufficient The banker will prefer cSufficient if the cost of maintaining extra capital, proportional to γ, is not too high.

It is important to understand the economic logic behind the choice between cmin and cSufficient. The point cmin gives lower capital, so the bank saves on its cost. But the bank has to take the safe project (socially optimal but less beneficial to shareholders) to avoid the capital adjustment cost. Should a bank switch to cSufficient, it would voluntarily choose to incur the cost of holding higher capital because that would enable the bank to take higher risk. Indeed, the bank will choose the risky project because it is not anymore constrained by the threat of capital adjustment cost. We have therefore established that, in the presence of tail risk, banks may choose to accumulate capital in order to be able to take tail risk.

With this is mind, we can now turn to optimal capital regulation. Recall that the level of capital that allows to rule out bank risk-taking through “skin in the game” only, c**, is not plausible.

Therefore, the only objective of regulation that is feasible in our setup is to assure that the bank’s capital is in the [c*, cSufficient) interval where a bank takes the safe project due to its aversion to capital adjustment costs. Both below and above this interval, the bank will undertake the risky project. Such a regulatory outcome can be implemented with two instruments. The first is a standard minimal capital requirement, set at cmin= c* (there is no reason to set cmin > c* since capital is costly). The second is an effective constraint on the bank’s excess capital over the minimal capital requirement. The constraint can be interpreted, in practice, not as a limit, but as special attention that regulators should give to banks with excess capital, anticipating that such banks are more likely than others to take tail risk. We summarize with the conjecture:

In the presence of tail risk, optimal capital regulation combines a minimal capital requirement cmin= c*and effective constraints on banks with excess capital (above cSufficient) to prevent them from taking tail risk.

VI. Conclusion

This paper examined the relationship between bank capital and risk-taking when banks have access to tail risk projects. We showed that traditional capital regulation becomes less effective in controlling bank risk because banks never internalize the negative realizations of tail risk projects. Moreover, we have suggested novel channels for unintended effects of higher capital: it enables banks to take higher tail risk without the fear of breaching the minimal capital requirement in mildly bad (i.e., non-tail) project realizations. The results are consistent with stylized facts about pre-crisis bank behavior, and have implications for the design of bank regulation.

References

  • Acharya, Viral V. (2003), Is the International Convergence of Capital Adequacy Regulation Desirable?, Journal of Finance, 58(6), 2745-2782.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Acharya, Viral V. (2009), A Theory of Systemic Risk and Design of Prudential Bank Regulation, Journal of Financial Stability, 5(3), 224-255.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Acharya, Viral V., Thomas Cooley, Matthew Richardson, and Ingo Walter (2009), Manufacturing Tail Risk: A Perspective on the Financial Crisis of 2007-2009, Foundations and Trends in Finance, 4(4), 247-325.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Acharya, Viral V., Lasse H. Pedersen, Thomas Philippon, and Matthew Richardson (2010), Measuring Systemic Risk, Federal Reserve Bank of Cleveland Working Paper.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Acharya, Viral V. and Matthew Richardson (2009), Restoring Financial Stability: How to Repair a Failed System?, An Independent View from New York University Stern School of Business, John Wiley & Sons.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Acharya, Viral V. and Tanju Yorulmazer (2007), Too Many to Fail–An Analysis of Time-Inconsistency in Bank Closure Policies, Journal of Financial Intermediation, 16(1), 1-31.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Adrian, Tobias and Markus K. Brunnermeier (2009), CoVaR, Mimeo, Princeton University.

  • Angora, Alain, Isabelle Distinguin, and Clovis Rugemintwari (2009), Excess Capital of European Banks: Does Bank Heterogeneity Matter?, Working Paper.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Asquith, Paul and David W. Mullins, Jr. (1986), Equity Issues and Offering Dilution, Journal of Financial Economics, 15, 61-89.

  • Berger, Allen, Robert DeYoung, Mark Flannery, Ozde Oztekin, and David Lee (2008), Why Do Large Banking Organizations Hold So Much Capital, Journal of Financial Services Research, 34, 123-150.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Bichsel, Robert and Jurg Blum (2004), The Relationship Between Risk and Capital in Swiss Commercial Banks: A Panel Study, Applied Financial Economics, 14, 591-597.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Basel Committee on Banking Supervision and Financial Stability Board (2010), Assessing the Macroeconomic Impact of the Transition to Stronger Capital and Liquidity Requirements Interim Report.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • BIS (2010), Group of Governors and Heads of Supervision Announces Higher Global Minimum Capital Standards, Bank for International Settlements, http://bis.org/press/p100912.htm.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Blum, Jurg (1999), Do Capital Adequacy Requirements Reduce Risk in Banking?, Journal of Banking and Finance, 23(5), 755-771.

  • Boot, Arnoud W.A. and Stuart I. Greenbaum (1993), Bank Regulation, Reputation, and Rents: Theory and Policy Implications, in Capital Markets and Financial Intermediation, ed. C. Mayer and X. Vives, Cambridge University Press.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Brunnermeier, Markus and Lasse H. Pedersen (2008), Market Liquidity and Funding Liquidity, Review of Financial Studies, 22(6), 2201-2238.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Caminal, Ramon and Carmen Matutes (2002), Market Power and Banking Failures, International Journal of Industrial Organization, 20(9), 1341-1361.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • De Jonghe, Olivier (2010), Back to the Basics in Banking? A Micro-Analysis of Banking System Stability, Journal of Financial Intermediation, 19(3), 387-417.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Dewatripont, Mathias and Jean Tirole (1994), The Prudential Regulation of Banks, MIT Press.

  • Flannery, Mark (1989), Capital Regulation and Insured Banks’ Choice of Individual Loan Default Risks, Journal of Monetary Economics, 24(2), 235-258.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Furlong, Frederick and Simon Kwan (2005), Market-to-Book, Charter Value, and Bank Risk-Taking – A Recent Perspective, Federal Reserve Bank of San Francisco, Working Paper.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Gorton, Gary (2010), Slapped in the Face by the Invisible Hand: Banking and the Panic of 2007, Oxford University Press, USA.

  • Hellmann, Thomas F., Kevin C. Murdock, and Joseph E. Stiglitz (2000), Liberalization, Moral Hazard in Banking, and Prudential Regulation: Are Capital Requirements Enough?, American Economic Review, 90(1), 147-165.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Holmstrom, Bengt and Jean Tirole (1997), Financial Intermediation, Loanable Funds and the Real Sector, The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112(3), 663-691.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Huang, Rocco and Lev Ratnovski (2009), Why Are Canadian Banks More Resilient?, IMF Working Paper 09/152.

  • Huang, Rocco and Lev Ratnovski (2011), The Dark Side of Bank Wholesale Funding, Journal of Financial Intermediation, 20(2), 248-263

  • IMF [International Monetary Fund] (2010), Technical Note on Stress Testing, Publication of Financial Sector Assessment Program Documentation, IMF Country Report No. 10/244, July 2010.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Jensen, Michael C. (1986), Agency Costs of Free Cash Flow, Corporate Finance, and Takeovers, American Economic Review, 76(2), 323-329.

  • Jensen, Michael C. and William H. Meckling (1976), Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure, Journal of Financial Economics, 3(4), 305-360.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Kahane, Yehuda (1977), Capital Adequacy and the Regulation of Financial Intermediaries, Journal of Banking and Finance, 1, 207-218.

  • Keeley, Michael C. (1990), Deposit Insurance, Risk, and Market Power in Banking, American Economic Review, 80(5), 1183-1200.

  • Kim, Daesik and Anthony M. Santomero (1988), Risk in Banking and Capital Regulation, Journal of Finance, 43, 1219-1233.

  • Knaup, Martin and Wolf Wagner (2010), Measuring the Tail Risks of Banks, Working Paper.

  • Koehn, Michael and Anthony M. Santomero (1980), Regulation of Bank Capital and Portfolio Risk, Journal of Finance, 35, 1235-1244.

  • Matutes, Carmen and Xavier Vives (2000), Imperfect Competition, Risk Taking, and Regulation in Banking, European Economic Review, 44, 1-34.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Myers, Stewart and Nicholas Majluf (1984), Corporate Financing and Investment Decisions When Firms Have Information that Investors Do Not Have, Journal of Financial Economics, 13(2), 187-221.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Perotti, Enrico and Javier Suarez (2009), Liquidity Risk Charges as a Macro Prudential Tool, CEPR Policy Insight, 40.

  • Perotti, Enrico and Javier Suarez (2010), A Pigovian Approach to Liquidity Regulation, CEPR Discussion Papers 8271.

  • Repulo, Rafael (2004), Capital Requirements, Market Power, and Risk-Taking in Banking, Journal of Financial Intermediation, 13, 156-182.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Rochet, Jean-Charles (2004), Macroeconomic Shocks and Banking Supervision, Journal of Financial Stability, 1(1), 93-110.

  • Shin, Hyun Song (2009), Reflections on Northern Rock: The Bank Run that Heralded the Global Financial Crisis, Journal of Economic Perspectives, 23(1), 101-119.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation

Appendix I: Proofs

A. Proof of Proposition 1

Consider first the case when c > 1 − RL. The relevant incentive compatibility condition derived from (5) becomes RS − (1 − c) ≥ p·[RH − (1 − c) + (1 − pµ)·[RL− (1 − c)], which can be rewritten as c1RSpRH(1pμ)RLμ.. We denote cT=0=1RSpRH(1=pμ)RLμ.. The threshold exists and is strictly larger than 1−RL for values of RS satisfying (6). Hence, for RS < pRH + (1 − p)RL,∃cT=0∈ (1 − RL, 1) such that ∀ c ∈ (1 − RL, cT=0) the risky project is selected and ∀ c ∈[cT=0, 1] the safe project is chosen. Otherwise, if (6) is not fulfilled, the bank selects the safe project ∀ c ∈(1 − RL, 1].

Consider now the case c ≤ − RL. The relevant incentive compatibility condition derived from (5) is RS − (1− c) ≥ p · [RH −((1 − c). The condition is equivalent with c1RSpRH1p.. We denote cTraditionalT=0=1RSpRH1p.. The threshold exists and is below or equal to 1 − RL for values of RS satisfying (7). Thus, for RspRH + (1−p)RL, cTraditionalT=0[0,1RL] such that c[0,cTraditionalT=0) the risky project is selected and ∀ c[cTraditionalT=0,1RL] the safe project is chosen. Otherwise, if (7) is not fulfilled, the bank selects the risky project ∀ c ∈ [0, 1 − RL].

To sum up, when (6) is fulfilled, ∃cT=0 ∈ (1 − RL, 1] such that ∀ c ∈[0, cT=0) the risky project is selected and ∀ c ∈ [cT=0, 1) the safe project is chosen. Likewise, when (6) is not fulfilled, cTraditionalT=0[0,1RL] such that c[0,cTraditionalT=0) the risky project is selected and ∀ c[cTraditionalT=0,1] the safe project is chosen.

B. Proof of Proposition 2

We consider two scenarios in turn. We start by analyzing a scenario in which the cost of recapitalization is such that μ1pcminRL<T<cminRL. Subsequently we show that our results are similar for Tμ1pcminRL. Both cases follow from assumption (13) of low adjustment cost.

μ1pcminRL<T<cminRL

We study bank’s behavior for three levels of initial capital: low (i.e.,ccRecapitallize), intermediate (i.e.,cRecapitalize < c < cSufficient) and high (i.e., ccSufficient).

Consider first the case when c ∈[0, cRecapitalize]. The banker never finds optimal to recapitalize for low realization of the risky project. The relevant incentive compatibility condition derived from (16) is RS − (1 − c) ≥ p· [RH − (1 − c)], where the left-hand side is the return on investing in the safe project and the right-hand side is the expected return on selecting the risky project. The condition can be rewritten as c1RSpRH1p.. We denote c1*=1RSpRH1p.. The threshold c1* and only if the next two constraints are jointly satisfiexists if and only if the next two constraints are jointly satisfied:

RS<1p+pRH,(T1a)
RS>pRH+(1p)(RLT).(T1a)

The former condition guarantees a positive c1*, while the latter forces the threshold to be lower than cRecapitalize, the upper limit for the interval we analyze. If (T1a’) is not fulfilled, then c1*<0 and ∀ c ∈ [0, cRecapitalize, the bank prefers the safe project. If (T1a) is not fulfilled, then c1*>cRecapitalize and ∀ c ∈ [0, cRecapitalize] the bank invests risky. When both constraints are simultaneously satisfied, c1*[0,cRecapitalize] such that c[0,c1*) the risky project is selected and c[c1*,cRecapitalize] the safe project is chosen. Assumption (2) implies that (T1a’) is always fulfilled.

Consider now the case when c ∈(cRecapitalize,cSufficient). The banker finds optimal to recapitalize for low realization RL. The relevant incentive compatibility condition is RS − (1 − c) ≥ p · [RH − (1 − c)] + (1 − pµ)·[RL − (1 − c) − T], with the certain return on choosing the safe project depicted on the left-hand side, and expected return on investing in the risky project depicted on the right-hand side. Rearranging terms the condition can be rewritten as c1RSpRH(1pμ)(RLT)μ.. We denote c2*=1RSpRH(1pμ)(RLT)μ. Similarly with the previous case, the threshold c2* exists if and only if it is simultaneously higher and lower than the lower and the higher boundary of the analyzed interval, respectively. The conditions are as follows:

RS<pRH=(1p)(RLT),(T2a)
RS>pRH+(1p)(RLT)+μ(TcminRL).(T2b)

Condition (T2a) is the opposite of (T1a). Thus, a satisfied condition (T1a) implies that (T2a) is not fulfilled. Condition (T2a) not satisfied implies that c2*<cRecapitalize and ∀ c ∈ (cRecapitalize, cSufficient), the bank prefers the safe project. If the second condition is not fulfilled, then c2*>cSufficient and ∀ c ∈ (cRecapitalize, cSufficient) the bank invests risky. When both constraints are simultaneously satisfied, c2*(cRecapitalize,cSufficient) such that c(cRecapitalize,c2*) the risky project is selected. The safe project is preferred ∀ c[c2*,cSufficient).

Consider now the final interval, when c ∈ [cSufficient, 1]. For low realization RL the bank always complies with the regulatory requirements. No additional capital is needed. The relevant incentive compatibility condition is RS − (1 − c) ≥ p · [RH − (1 − c)+(1 − pµ) · [RL − (1 − c)]. Rearranging terms the condition becomes c1RSpRH(1pμ)RLμ.. We denote c** = 1RSpRH(1pμ)RLμ.. The threshold c** exists if and only if c** > cSufficient and c**< 1. The later is always fulfilled following from the assumption (1)of higher NPV for the safe project. The former condition is depicted in (T3a) below. When (T3a) is not satisfied, the bank prefers the safe project for any level of initial capital larger than cSufficient. Otherwise,∀ c ∈ [cSufficient, c**) the risky project is selected, while the safe project is preferred ∀ c ∈[c**, 1].

RS<pRH+(1p)RLμcminRL.(T3a)

Next we discuss the process of project selection. Recall that Z = pRH + (1 − p)(RLT) + µ(Tcmin RL) and W = pRH + (1 − p)RLµcminRL, from (18) and (17), respectively. We also denote B = pRH +(1 − p)(RLT). Under assumption (13), Z < B < W. We distinguish among four possible scenarios.

Scenario S1: RS < Z. As a consequence, condition (T2b) is not satisfied and ∀ c ∈ (cRecapitalize, cSufficient) the bank selects the risky project. RS < Z also implies that RS > B and RS < W. Condition (T1a) is not satisfied but (T3a) is. As a result, the bank invests risky ∀ c ∈ [0, cSufficient] ∪ [cSufficient, c**), and the bank invests safe ∀ c ∈ [c**, 1].

Scenario S2: ZRSB. The right-hand side implies that condition (T1a) is not satisfied. For initial capital c lower than cRecapitalize the bank prefers the risky project. The left hand side implies that condition (T2b) is fulfilled. Also condition (T2a) is satisfied being the opposite of (T1a). Hence, we can conclude that ∃ c* ∈ (cRecapitalize, cSufficient) with c*=c2*, such that ∀ c ∈ (cRecapitalize, c*) the risky project is selected, while the safe project is preferred ∀ c ∈ [c*, cSufficient). Condition (T3a) is also satisfied. Similarly with the previous scenario, the bank invests risky ∀ c ∈ [cSufficient, c**), and safe ∀ c ∈ [c**, 1].

Scenario S3: B < RS < W. The left hand-side implies that condition (T1a) is satisfied. We can argue that ∃ c* ∈ (0, c Recapitalize) with c*=c1*, such that ∀ c ∈ [0, c*) the risky project is selected, while the safe project is preferred ∀ c ∈ [c*, cRecapitalize]. Condition (T1a) implies that (T2a) is not satisfied. Thus, ∀ c ∈ (cRecapitalize, cSufficient) the safe project will be selected. The bank investment decision is identical with the one from previous scenarios when the level of capital is high enough (i.e., c larger than cSufficient).

Scenario S4: RSW. Neither condition (T3a) nor condition (T2a) are satisfied anymore. The bank selects the safe project ∀ c ∈ (cRecapitalize, 1]. However, condition (T1a) is fulfilled. Hence, ∃ c* ∈[0, cRecapitalize] with c*=c1*, such that ∀ c ∈ [0, c*) the risky project is selected, while the safe project is preferred ∀ c ∈ [c*, cRecapitalize].

The values for thresholds c* and c** for Case (a) of Proposition 2, are derived under Scenario S2 above, for ZRSB.

Tμ1pcminRL

We consider now the scenario under which the cost of recapitalization is very low. Lowering T has no quantitative impact on cSufficient and cRecapitalize, the thresholds in initial capital which trigger bank’s decision between raising additional capital or letting the regulator to overtake the bank. Their relative position is unchanged: cSufficient is larger than cRecapitalize following from easily verifiable identity μ1pcminRL<cminRL combined with our restriction on T. However, the process of project selection under assumption (13) is marginally affected. In this scenario Z < W < B, as a consequence of lower T. As discussed before, we distinguish among four possible scenarios (S1’) RS < Z,(S2’) ZRS < W, (S3’) WRS < B and (S4’) RS > B. Discussions for scenarios S1’, S2’ and S4’ are identical with our previous discussion for scenarios S1, S2, and S4. We discuss scenario S3’ next. WRS implies that condition (T3a) is not satisfied. Hence, the bank prefers the safe project for any level of initial capital larger than cSufficient. RS < B implies that condition (T1a) is not satisfied. For initial capital c lower than cRecapitalize the bank prefers the risky project. However, condition (T2a) is satisfied being the opposite of (T1a), and also condition (T2b) is implied by the fact that W > Z. Hence, we can conclude that ∃ c*∈ (cRecapitalize, cSufficient)with c*=c2*, such that ∀ c ∈(cRecapitalize, c*) the risky project is selected, while the safe project is preferred ∀ c ∈[c*, cSufficient).

C. Analysis of the robustness of results of Proposition 2

We offer here a discussion for the results of Proposition 2. We analyze bank’s project choice for the case of high cost of recapitalization: T > cmin RL; we show that our results are robust to this specification. Recall that under assumption (13), there exist values of c such that cRecapitalize < c < cSufficient where the banker chooses to recapitalize the bank following the RL realization instead of abandoning it. We show next that when T is larger than cmin RL the banker always a bandons a bank with in sufficient capital. Although the main results from Proposition 2 are not qualitatively affected, higher recapitalization cost has a quantitative impact on our results. Therefore, we start by deriving the new conditions which drive these results. It is optimal for the bank to raise additional capital (if this was demanded by the regulator) when conditions cL < cmin and (11) are simultaneously satisfied. The former condition implies that c < 1 − RL (1 − cmin), while from the latter c > 1 + TRL. Under our modified assumption of high cost of recapitalization T, these conditions can not be satisfied simultaneously. For any levels of initial capital c below 1 − RL(1 − cmin), the bank receives a request for adding extra capital but she never finds optimal to do so because such an action will not generate positive payoffs. As a result, the bank is closed and the shareholder expropriated. Conversely, when the level of initial capital is above 1 − RL(1 − cmin) the banking authority doesn’t take any corrective action against the bank since returns RL are above the critical level Rmin. We denote:

cNEWRecapitalize=1RL(1cmin),(22)

where cNEWRecapitalize(0,1). Next, we explore the bank’s project choice for levels of initial capital below and above this critical threshold.

Consider first the case when c(0,cNEWRecapitalize).. The bank never recapitalizes for the low realization of the risky project. The bank would have incentive to select the safe project when RS − (1 − c) ≥ p[RH − (1 − c)], which implies that initial capital c to be larger than 1RSpRH1p.. We previously denoted c1*=1RSpRH1p.. This threshold exists if and only if (T1a’) and the following condition are jointly satisfied:

RS>pRH+(1p)RL(1cmin).(T1a NEW)

The second condition guarantees that c1* is lower than cNEWRecapitalize, the upper boundary for the nterval we analyze. For large returns on the safe project (i.e., condition (T1a’) is not fulfilled), c(0,cNEWRecapitalize), the bank prefers the safe project. If (T1a NEW) is not fulfilled, then ∀ c(0,cNEWRecapitalize) the bank invests risky. Otherwise, when both constraints are simultaneously satisfied, c(0,c1*) the risky project is selected and c(c1*,cNEWRecapitalize) the safe project is chosen. Our assumption (2) implies that (T1a’) is always fulfilled.

Consider now the second case when c(cNEWRecapitalize,1).. The bank always complies with the regulatory requirements when RL is obtained due to high initial capital. No additional capital is needed. The bank would have incentive to select the safe project when RS − (1 − c) ≥ p[RH − (1 − c)] + (1 − pµ)[RL − (1 − c)], which implies c1RSpRH(1pμ)RLμ.. We previously denoted c**=1RSpRH(1pμ)RLμ.. The threshold c** exists if and only if condition (T3a) is satisfied. The safe project is preferred for any level of initial capital larger than cNEWRecapitalize whenever (T3a) is not satisfied. Otherwise, c(cNEWRecapitalize,c**) the risky project is selected, while the safe project is preferred ∀ c ∈ (c**, 1).

Recall that W = pRH + (1 − p)RLµcmin RL. We also denote Q = pRH + (1 − p) RL(1 − cmin). It is easy to show that Q < W due to the identity 1 − pµ >0. We distinguish among only three possible scenarios.

Scenario S1”: RSQ. As a consequence, condition (T1a NEW) is not satisfied and ∀ c(0,cNEWRecapitalize) the bank selects the risky project. RS < Q implies that RS < W Condition (T3a) is satisfied. As a result, the bank invests risky c(cNEWRecapitalize,c**), while she prefers the safe project ∀ c ∈ (c**, 1).

Scenario S2”: Q < RS < W· The left hand-side implies that condition (T1a NEW) is satisfied. This implies that c*(0,cNEWRecapitalize) with c*=c1*, such that ∀ c ∈ (0, c*) the risky project is selected, while the safe project is preferred. c(c*,cNEWRecapitalize). Similarly with the previous scenario, the bank invests risky c(cNEWRecapitalize,c**), and safe ∀ c ∈ (c**,1). This result is implied by RS being lower than W.

Scenario S3”: RSW. Condition (T1a NEW) is satisfied while condition (T3a) is not. Hence, the bank selects the risky projects, ∀ c ∈ (0, c*), with c*=c1*, and she selects the safe project ∀ c ∈ (c*, 1).

To conclude, we can argue that the qualitative results of Proposition 2 are valid under the relaxed assumption. Nevertheless, condition (T2b) has to be replaced by the relevant condition (T1a NEW).

D. Bank’s choice when the return on safe project is large

Let us consider here that the return on the safe asset is large, that is RS > 1 − p + pRH. This drives the following results under Assumption (13): (1) condition (T1a’) is not satisfied, implying that ∀ c ∈ [0, cRecapitalize], the bank prefers the safe project; (2) condition (T1a) is satisfied, which implies that condition (T2a) is not and as a result ∀ c ∈(cRecapitalize, cSufficient), the bank prefers the safe project; (3) condition (T3a) is not satisfied and as a consequence ∀ c ∈ [cSufficient, 1], the bank invests in the safe project. Summing up, for any levels of initial capital c, the bank prefers the safe project when the certain return RS is high enough.

E. Proof of Proposition 3

From equation (10), cSufficient > cmin. We consider three cases for the level of cmin Consider first the case when cmincRecapitalize. From Case (a) of Proposition 2, the banker finds optimal to select the risky project when the level of initial capital is in this region. The banker’s expected payoff is p. [RH − (1 − c)] − , which is decreasing in initial capital c (the first derivative is negative since γ > 1 by assumption (A)). Hence, under minimal capital ratio regulation, the banker chooses cmin as initial capital.

Consider now the case when cmin ∈(cRecapitalize,c*). Again, from Case (a) of Proposition 2, the banker finds optimal to select the risky project and recapitalize in the RL realization. The banker’s expected payoff is p·[RH − (1 − c)] + (1 − pµ)[RL − (1 − c) − T] − , which is decreasing in initial capital c. Hence, under minimal capital ratio regulation, the banker chooses again cmin as initial capital.

Consider now the last case when cmin ∈ [c*, cSufficient). The banker finds optimal to take no risk. The safe project is selected and the expected payoff for the banker is RS − (1 − c) − · The expected payoff decreases in c. However, the banker can be better off selecting a higher level of initial capital. Consider that the banker decides to hold cSufficient. This allows risk-taking (see Case (a) from Proposition 2). The expected payoff is p·[RH − (1 − cSufficient)] + (1 − pµ)·[RL − (1 − cSufficient)] − cSufficientγ. The banker is better off selecting a higher level of capital if and only if

p.[RH(1cSufficient)]+(1pμ).[RL(1cSufficient)]cSufficientγ>RS(1cmin)cminγ.(23)

Rearranging terms in (23), the condition becomes γ<1+μRL1RLRSpRH(1pμ)RL(1cmin)(1RL. We denote γ*=1+μRL1RLRLpRH(1pμ)RL(1cmin)(1RL).. The threshold γ* is higher than 1 for RS < W, with W given in (17)-see also Case (a)of Proposition 2 for further details. Therefore, we can conclude that ∃ γ* ∈ (1, ∞) such that ∀ γ ∈ (1, γ*) the banker selects c = cSufficient and ∀ γ ∈ [γ*,∞)the banker selects c = cmin.

Appendix II: Extensions

We offer here two extensions for our model and examine the implications of charter value and of different specification for recapitalization costs. We show that our results are robust to these generalizations.

A. Charter value

In Section 2 we have assumed that there is no charter value for the continuation of bank’s activity. In this section we introduce a positive charter value V > 0 and show that our results are robust to this extension. Our model suggests that low competition in banking, which provides a high charter value, leads to investment in the efficient safe project even by well-capitalized banks.

The role of banks’ franchise values have been shown relevant in other studies. Hellmann et al. (2000) and Repullo (2004) argue that prudent behavior can be facilitated by increasing banks’ charter value. They study the links between capital requirements, competition for deposits, charter value and risk-taking incentives, and point out that banks are more likely to gamble and to take more risk in a competitive banking system, since competition erodes profits and implicitly the franchise value. A similar idea is put forward by Matutes and Vives (2000). They argue that capital regulation should be complemented by deposit rate regulation and direct asset restrictions in order to efficiently keep risk-taking under control. Acharya (2003) explores how continuation value affects risk preferences in the context of optimal regulation, and demonstrates the disciplinating effect of charter value on bank risk-taking. Finally, Keeley (1990) and Furlong and Kwan (2005) explore empirically the relation between charter value and different measures of bank risk, and find strong evidence that bank charter value disciplined bank risk-taking.

In the new setting, the banker’s payoff to the safe project after repaying depositors becomes SV=RS(1c)+V. The banker’s payoff to the risky project is as follows: when RH is realized, the banker gets HV=RH(1c)+V, while the payoff is 0 for extremely low realization R0·When the low return RL is realized and capital is positive but insufficient ex-post, the banker prefers to recapitalize at a cost T for lower levels of initial capital c. The reason for this is that banker’s expected payoff increases by V if bank is not closed by the regulator. Hence, the bank raises additional capital when initial capital c is higher than cVRecapitalize, where:

cVRecapitalize=1+TRLV,(24)

and cVRecapitalize<cRecapitalize.. On the other hand, the threshold point cSufficient does not change since it is given by the exogenous regulation.

We make the simplifying assumption that the charter value is not larger than a certain threshold:

V<1+TRL.(25)

This makes threshold cVRecapitalize positive and assures the existence for the area [0,cVRecapitalize] where the bank is abandoned for low realization of the risky project. Consider the area (cVRecapitalize,cSufficient). When initial capital c is in this range, a bank which is subject to regulator’s corrective action prefers to raise additional capital. Since cVRecapitalizecSufficient,, while right boundary of the interval is left unchanged by any increase in V, we can argue that any reduction in banking competition, which increases bank charter value, makes the decision to raise fresh capital more likely.

We introduce the following two thresholds:

ZV=pRH+(1p)(RLT)+μ(TVcminRL),(26)

as the new threshold for the binding impact of the prompt corrective action (with ZV < Z), and

B=pRH+(1p)(RLT).(27)

Following a similar proof as for Proposition 2, we can show that there exist two thresholds cV* and cV** for the level of initial bank capital such that under assumption (13) and for levels of return on the safe project satisfying ZV < RS < B, with ZV and B defined in (26) and (27), respectively, the bank’s investment preference is as follows:

(a) the bank prefers the risky project for 0c<cV*, while for cV*c<cSufficient the safe project is preferred, with cV*(cVRecapitalize,cSufficient), where cVRecapitalize and cSufficient are defined in (24) and (10), respectively, and

cV*=1VRSpRH(1pμ)(RLT)μ,(28)

(b) the bank prefers the risky project for cSufficientc<cV**, and the safe project for ccV**, where cV**(cSufficient,1)

cV**=1VRSpRH(1pμ)RLμ.(29)

Observe that a positive charter value has a negative impact on all relevant thresholds which drive bank’s preferences (i.e., cVRecapitalize,cV*, and cV**), except for cSufficient. Hence, we can argue that higher charter value plays the role of a counterbalancing force to the risk-taking incentives generated by the presence of risky projects with heavy left tails. This means that when the continuation value of bank’s activity is high enough, both intervals (0,cV*) and (cSufficient,cV**) shrink. This suggests that low competition in the banking industry induces banks with larger capital buffers to take less risk.

In summary, the results of our basic model are therefore robust to the introduction of charter value, conditional on the fact that this value is not too large. Large values of charter value reduces risk-taking incentives even for well-capitalized banks.

B. Concave capital adjustment cost

In Section 2 we considered a simple fixed cost of recapitalization. We now show that results are robust to a more general specification of this cost function.

In this section we discuss a variation of the model in which the cost of recapitalization has a fixed and a variable component. The variable component is proportional to the amount of new capital that the bank has to raise in order to comply with the minimal capital ratio. Specifically, the bank has to raise a capital level RminRL, where Rmin equals:

Rmin=1c1cmin.(30)

The above threshold is derived from the condition of a minimal capital ratio of cmin (i.e., ccmin = [Rmin − (1 − c)]/Rmin), by solving for the value of bank’s assets (i.e., Rmin).7 In this new setting, the recapitalization cost is concave in capital level, and has the following specification:

Cost(c,RL)=T+β(1c1cminRL)(31)

We assume that variable cost of recapitalization (i.e., β) is positive and not as low as to make the banker abandon the bank regardless the level of initial capital:

T<RL(1+β).(32)

The banker’s payoff from the safe project, as well as the realizations of the risky project are the same as in the basic model. However, when the low realization RL is obtained, the bank is abandoned more often than in the basic model due to higher cost of recapitalization. The bank is closed when c<cCCRecapitalize, where:

cCCRecapitalize=1+TRL(1+β)1+β1cmin,(33)

(with CC for concave cost).

Under assumption (13), cCCRecapitalize>cRecapitalize. On the other hand, the level of capital which guarantees that the bank satisfies ex-post the regulatory minimal upon realization of RL (i.e., cSufficient) remains unchanged. Hence, the interval (cCCRecapitalize,cSufficient) shrinks, suggesting that the bank is less likely to raise additional capital if required to do so.

We denote:

BCC=pRH+(1p)RL(1+β)T1+β1cmin.(34)

Following the lines of proof for Proposition 2 we can show that exist two thresholds cCC* and cCC** for the level of initial bank capital such that under assumption (13) and for level of return on the safe project satisfying Z < RS < BCC, with Z and BCC defined in (18) and (34), respectively, the bank’s investment preference is as follows:

(a) the bank prefers the risky project for 0c<cCC*, while for cCC*c<cSufficient the safe project is preferred, with cCC*(cCCRecapitalize,cSufficient), where cCCRecapitalize and cSufficient are defined in (33) and (10), respectively, and

cCC*=1RSpRH(1pμ)[RL(1+β)T]μβ1cmin(1pμ);(35)

(b) the bank prefers the risky project for cSufficientc<cCC*,, and the safe project for ccCC**, where cCC**(cSufficient,1) and cCC**=c**, with c** defined in (20).

Observe that the introduction of a variable component for recapitalization cost leaves both boundaries of the interval (cSufficient,cCC**) unchanged. Thus, our model is robust to this specification and a concave cost of recapitalization does not affect the risk-taking incentives of well-capitalized banks when projects exhibiting heavier left tails are available for investment.

1

Mr. Perotti is with the University of Amsterdam and the Dutch Central Bank. Mr. Vlahu is with the Dutch Central Bank. We thank Douglas Gale, Andrew Winton, Stijn Claessens, Giovanni Dell’Ariccia, Dale Gray, Alexander Guembel, Thomas Nitschka, Javier Suarez, as well as participants at seminars at DNB, IMF, 14th Swiss Society for Financial Markets conference, IJCB 3rd Financial Stability conference, 2011 International Risk Management conference, 2011 Finlawmetrics conference and 2011 IFABS conference for helpful comments. Any errors are ours. Vlahu gratefully acknowledges financial support by the Gieskes-Strijbis Foundation. The views expressed in this paper are those of the authors and should not be attributed to the Dutch Central Bank or the International Monetary Fund.

2

The fact that adjustment costs of bank equity raising are significant was highlighted, for example, in the Basel Committee-FSF (2010) assessment of the impact of the transition to stronger capital requirements.

3

Recent studies develop different measures for banks’ tail risk. Acharya and Richardson (2009), Adrian and Brunnermeier (2009), and De Jonghe (2010) compute realized tail risk exposure over a certain period by using historical evidence of tail risk events, while Knaup and Wagner (2010) propose a forward-looking measure for bank tail risk.

4

The presence of not fully risk-based deposit insurance is an inherent feature of most contemporary banking systems, and one of main rationales for bank regulation (Dewatripont and Tirole, 1994).

5

The assumption that project choice is unobservable while project returns are, is a standard approach to modelling (Hellman et al. 2000, Rochet 2004).

6

We re-write cT=0(μ)=1constμ, with const=RS −E(R). The degree of polynomial cT=0(µ) is given by limμμ·[cT=0(μ)]cT=0(μ) equals 0, the degree of the logrithm function.

7

Consider the following example. Assume that the bank has to raise δ units of capital to satisfy the regulatory minimum when RL is realized. Hence, cmin=RL(1c)+δRL+δ.. This implies that RL+δ=1c1cmin, which equals Rmin according to (30). We can conclude that δ=RminRL.

Capital Regulation and Tail Risk
Author: Mr. Enrico Camillo Perotti, Mr. Lev Ratnovski, and Mr. Razvan Vlahu
  • View in gallery

    The timeline

  • View in gallery

    The two opposite effects of capital on bank risk-taking

  • View in gallery

    Tail risk and the initial capital required to prevent risk-shifting

  • View in gallery

    Bank’s recapitalization decision and payoffs

    The bank’s recapitalization decision and banker’s payoffs as a function of initial capital c, upon the realization of low return RL are as follows. For ccSufficient, the bank has positive and sufficient capital at date ½. The bank continues to date 1, repays depositors and obtains a positive payoff. For c < cSufficient, the bank has positive and insufficient or negative capital. The bank can be either abandoned or recapitalized. The bank is abandoned for ccRecapitalize. As a result the bank is closed and the banker gets a zero payoff. The bank is recapitalized at a cost for cRecapitalize < c <cSufficient. The bank continues to date 1, repays depositors, pays the recapitalization cost, and obtains a positive payoff.

  • View in gallery

    Bank’s project choice

    The bank’s project choice depending on the level of initial capital, in Case (a) of Proposition 2: The relationship between bank capital and risk-taking is non-linear and is characterized by two thresholds as follows. When the level of capital is low (c<c*), the bank prefers the risky project, while for high level of capital (cc**) the safe project is chosen. For intermediate level of capital (c* ≤<c**), the bank prefers either the safe project (for c*c<cSufficient) or the risky one (for cSufficien tc <c**).

  • View in gallery

    Bank’s project choice when the risky project has a heavier left tail. Case 1

    A heavier left tail is characterized by a higher probability for the extremely low outcome (i.e., a higher µ). A change in the return profile of the risky project following a change in probability distribution (i.e., both p and µ are increased, other else equal, such that the expected value of the risky project remains the same), affects both thresholds c* and c* and c**. The interval [ cSufficient, c**) widens, suggesting that well-capitalized banks which behave prudently in absence of tail risk projects, have a strong incentive to undertake more risk, if projects with heavier left tail are available in economy.

  • View in gallery

    Bank’s project choice when the risky project has a heavier left tail. Case 2

    A heavier left tail is characterized by a higher probability for the extremely low outcome (i.e., a higher µ). A change in the return profile of the risky project following a change in probability distribution (i.e., µ is increased), compensated by higher RL and RH, other else equal, such that the expected value of the risky project remains the same, affects thresholds c* and c**, and cSufficient as well. The interval [cSufficient, c**) widens even more, suggesting that both well and less capitalized banks will start choosing the risky project.