Abstract
Financial innovation has increased diversification opportunities and lowered investment costs, but has not reduced the relative cost of active (informed) investment strategies relative to passive (less informed) strategies. What are the consequences? I study an economy with linear production technologies, some more risky than others. Investors can use low quality public information or collect high quality, but costly, private information. Information helps avoiding excessively risky investments. Financial innovation lowers the incentives for private information collection and deteriorates public information: the economy invests more often in excessively risky technologies. This changes the business cycle properties and can reduce welfare by increasing the likelihood of "liquidation crises"
I. Introduction
Financial innovation is “exemplified by new derivative contracts, new corporate securities, new forms of pooled investment products, […] or by new means of distributing securities and processing transactions” (Tufano [2002]). Indeed, in the last two decades, the US have witnessed a tremendous increase in the types of securities available to investors and a decrease in the cost of holding and trading them. Traditionally, economists have viewed the process of financial innovation as beneficial for two sets of reasons. First of all it spurs growth, thanks to the greater easiness with which funds flow from agents with low productive projects towards agents with high productive projects (Levine [1997], Rajan and Zingales [1998], Azariadis and Kass [2003], among others). Second, the amount of risk that investors bear is reduced, as a consequence of the availability of a broader menu of assets, allowing greater diversification and risk sharing (Merton [1987], Mendoza et al. [2008]). This traditional view has recently come under attack, particularly on the part where it predicates that financial development leads to risk reductions for investors. Indeed, some authors wonder whether financial development has made the world riskier and subject to “excessive risk taking” (Rajan [2005]), while others plainly state, with respect to securitization, that its “positive role […] in dispersing risk” is an “old view, now discredited” (Shin [2009]).
This paper intends to contribute to the ongoing debate by highlighting the role of costly information collection as a channel, largely neglected by the literature, through which financial innovation shapes the amount and types of risk that investors choose to hold, the characteristics of aggregate economic fluctuations and, finally, welfare. Using data provided by French [2008] I find evidence that, for the US stock market, financial innovation was not accompanied by a reduction in the relative cost of active (i.e. more informed) trading compared to the cost of passive (less informed) trading. What are the possible consequences of this phenomenon? To answer this question I develop a theoretical model where agents learn about the quality of investment opportunities by choosing either to be active investors and acquire costly private information or to be passive and rely on less costly, but less precise, public information. Information is valuable because it avoids making low quality investments, which are investments in excessively risky technologies. Following the literature on noisy trading (Grossman and Stiglitz [1980], Kyle [1985], Summers and Shleifer [1990]) the overall amount of private information collected by active investors determines a positive externality on the precision of the public information. Under various assumptions on assets returns, I show that financial innovation leads to a decrease in the amount on private information collection whenever it is not accompanied by a reduction in the cost of investing actively relative to the cost of investing passively. The reason is that information is a strategic substitute to risk diversification. Financial innovation has positive welfare effects because it provides “insurance” to investors, by allowing them to trade a larger set of assets and thus to better diversify risk. However, as in a standard moral hazard problem, greater insurance reduces incentives to take costly actions, such as collecting private information, to avoid excessively risky investments. This theoretical finding is supported by a growing body of literature (Cremers and Petajisto [2009], French[2008]) that shows how US stock market holdings have consistently shifted form active to passive forms of investment in the past 20 years. Information collection affects welfare and the business cycle properties. The lower amount of private information collected, working through the externality of public information, has a negative impact on the welfare of passive investors, thus partly counterbalancing their gains from better risk sharing. With lower information, agents more often mistakenly invest in technologies characterized by excessive systemic risk: I derive business cycles statistics which incorporate the effects of information collection on the volatility and sensitivity to systemic shocks of the aggregate productivity. With this respect, the model adds a new theoretical perspective to the literature on the great moderation (Stock and Watson [2002], Fogli and Perri [2006], Dynan et al. [2006], Stiroh [2009]).
Finally I show how, in a more dynamic setting with time varying risk, information cycles arise. Financial development tends to reduce information collection in periods where excess risk is mainly idiosyncratic (and thus “insurable” through better diversification), but has no impact on information collection in periods when excess risk is mainly systemic. Consequently, financial development increases the frequency of “liquidation crises”. These are situations when too risky investments are mistakenly undertaken in periods of idiosyncratic excess risk, only to be suddenly liquidated when excess risk becomes systemic and information collection soars. If liquidation crises impose aggregate costs to the economy, then financial development reduces welfare.
The remaining of the paper proceeds as follows. Section II reviews the empirical evidence, Section III presents technologies, preferences, information revelation mechanism and the equilibrium for the basic model. Section IV extends the basic model to time varying risk and analyzes liquidation crises. Section V concludes.
II. Empirical evidence
To substantiate our discussion, it is worthwhile to review a few points about financial innovation. To this end, the US is an interesting reference country for which we have quite abundant empirical evidence. The three facts that I emphasize are the following: a) there has been a tremendous increase in the menu of assets and in diversification possibilities available to investors b) liquidity and trading costs have trended downwards since the ‘60s, but c) the cost of active investment strategies has not decreased relative to the cost of passive strategies. Point a) is easily illustrated with some examples. High-yield bond issuances went from about $50 billions in 1993, when issuances were entirely in the US, to $180 billions in 2006, with the US share going down to 70% (BIS [2008]). During the same period, the value of worldwide buyouts transactions undertaken by private equity funds went from a scanty $30 billions to more than $800 billions (Kaplan and Strömberg [2009]). The US market for asset-backed securities, that in 1998 was worth $271 billion, increased four times in only a few years and reached over $1,200 billions in 2006 (Weaver [2008]). Securitization in the US mortgage market, virtually absent two decades ago, reached 80.5% of mortgages originated in 2006, for a total value of $2.4 trillions (Gorton [2008]). For the purpose of our discussion, the most important conclusion to be drawn is that the successful introduction of these new financial instruments (high-yield bonds, private equity, mortgage backed securities) opened up to investors new opportunities in markets (for high risk firms, unlisted companies, housing) that before had more limited access to external financing, mostly provided by very specialized investors (e.g. banks). A number of studies (for instance Jones [2002], French [2008]) confirm b) by establishing that trading costs in the stock market have decreased over time due to reductions in both bid-ask spreads and in trading fees. Things become more complicated when we want to investigate c), since it requires the difficult task of ranking investment strategies by their “information content” and then of calculating the corresponding cost. The most comprehensive attempt to estimate information costs has been done by French (2008), who reports cost series for various investment strategies in the US stock market. Using these data, I analyze two alternative cost measures for active and passive investments. The first is the cost of active and passive Defined Benefit pension plans, while the second is the cost of composite active and passive strategies comprising investments in mutual funds, pension funds, hedge funds and direct equity holding. Figure 1 presents the two cost measures, and Appendix E provides more details on their construction. The common message is the following: the absolute cost of passive strategies has been trending downwards over time, while the absolute cost of active strategies has decreased to a much lesser extent. Consequently, the relative cost of active strategies has significantly increased over time, roughly doubling in the period 1991-2006. Certainly, a more precise measure of information costs would take into consideration the possibility that active strategies might have become much better in producing information. Measuring information costs using this sort of quality-adjusted index could indeed reveal that active investment strategies have not become, relative to passive strategies, as costly as Figure 1 suggests. Nonetheless, as a first order approximation, it seems reasonable to argue that quality considerations would not be so strong as to invert the clear trend in Figure 1.
Cost of active and passive investment strategies (in % of investment) and relative cost of active strategies. Active and passive Defined Benefit pension funds (top). Composite active and passive strategies (bottom). The data used are from French (2008). Details on strategy construction are in Appendix E.
Citation: IMF Working Papers 2010, 266; 10.5089/9781455210732.001.A001
The next section presents the basic model relating information collection to financial innovation. The model will allow us to highlight the consequences for the agents’ risk taking behavior, for the business cycle and for welfare of a financial innovation process characterized by a)-b) and c).
III. The basic model
A. Technologies and information structure
The economy lasts two periods t = 1, 2 and is endowed with 2 N linear production technologies that use consumption goods at t =1 as input and produce consumption goods at t = 2 as output. Technologies are evenly distributed distributed across N markets m = 1,…, N, so that each market is associated with exactly two technologies j = 1, 2. Each technology is uniquely identified by a pair (m, j). In every market m, one technology is low risk and the other excess risk. The return on the excess risk technology in m is a mean preserving spread of the return on the low risk technology in m. The realization of a random type θm ∈ {1, 2} decides that technology j = θm is the excess risk technology in m (and thus j = 3 − θm is the low risk technology in m). Call Θ = (θ1,…, θN) the vector of types and T = {1, 2}N the set of such vectors. Call rm,j the return between t =1 and t = 2 of technology (m, j) and assume that
The random variables im and em are i.i.d. across markets, while S is the systemic shock common to all markets. All shocks are independent of each other. I normalize to unity the expected returns by assuming that E[im] = E [em] = E[S] = 1 and I denote with
Figure 2 gives a graphical representation of markets and technologies. The setup is open to various interpretations. For instance, markets can represent different products, or different groups of customers segmented by geographical area, wealth or income. For every market, some choices of the production and marketing technologies are more risky than others. For example, a certain production technology may rely too much on inputs whose prices are very volatile, or a certain marketing strategy may target customers whose payment ability is very uncertain. Excess risk is modeled as a mean preserving spread over the low risk technology, in fact
where the excess risk zm = im(emS − 1) satisfies
Economy divided in N = 4 markets. Within each market there are two linear technologies j = 1,2 with random productivity rm,j. The realized type is Θ = (2, 1, 2, 1) so technology j = 2 has excess risk in markets 1, 3 and j = 1 has excess risk in markets 2, 4.
Citation: IMF Working Papers 2010, 266; 10.5089/9781455210732.001.A001
Given a realization of rm,3−θm the source of excess risk in zm is twofold: excess idiosyncratic risk em and excess systemic risk1 S.
The joint distribution of types is summarized by a probability function F (Θ) that satisfies a symmetry condition
for every Θ ∈ T. Condition (3) simply requires that the probability of realization of a type Θ equals the probability of realization of its opposite type
We are ready to describe the information structure of the economy, i.e. the way in which information about the realization of Θ flows to the agents in the economy. For now, we conveniently assume that the information structure is exogenously imposed to the economy, but in Section D I will derive in detail the microeconomic mechanism that allows this structure to emerge as an equilibrium outcome of the model.
First of all, at the beginning of time 1 all agents are informed that the current realization of types satisfies Θ ∈ TΘ where
In other words, after the types are realized the only initial uncertainty for agents is whether the realized type is the true Θ or its opposite. Notice that, conditional on this information, assumption (3) implies that the two types are equally likely. Next, agents have two ways to further refine their knowledge. The first is to become an active investor, a choice that reduces the investor’s wealth to a fraction2 1/ξA of its original value, with ξA > 1, and allows the observation of a private signal IA(Θ) such that
Alternatively, an investor can choose to be passive. Passive investors face investment costs that reduce their wealth to a fraction 1/ξP, with 1 < ξP < ξA, but observe a public signal IP(Θ),
where Iρ is a binary random variable, independent on Θ, which equals 1 with probability ρ ∈ [0,1] and zero otherwise. Active investors are able to take fully informed investment decisions, but have to pay a high cost. Instead, passive investors pay a smaller cost but can rely only on the public signal IP, which is less precise. In fact, IP is informative if and only if I ρ = 1, an event realized with probability ρ, while if I ρ = 0 the public signal is uninformative and the types Θ and
Define η ∈ [0,1] the fraction of active investors at time 1. To make public information a positive spillover of private information collection I assume that
for AE ∈ (0,1). As mentioned above, the initial observability (4), the particular binary choices for the public signal IP ∈ {0, Θ} and the form of the spillover function (8) are all derived from first principles in Section D.
All agent have to pay a cost to access investment opportunities, but active agents, who have superior information, face higher costs. For this reason, we can identify with ξ > 1 the relative information cost, where
In terms of points b) and c) in Section II, financial innovation appears to be associated with in costs ξA and ξP, but not with a decrease in ξ. The remaining point a), relating financial innovation to greater diversification opportunities, can be modeled in the following way. Assume that each investor draws a specialization h in market h = 1,…, N. Call ph the fraction of investors with specialization h. Agents are constrained to invest at most a fraction
B. Preferences
Agents’ preferences are given by an homothetic utility function, which allows a parametric separation between risk aversion and intertemporal elasticity of substitution. Call {ct,I} any consumption process for time t = 1, 2 chosen by the agent after observing a signal I ∈ {0, Θ} at the beginning of time 1. Conditional on I, consumption c1,I is deterministic, but consumption c2,I is stochastic, since it depends on the random return at t = 2 of the agent’s investement. A conditional consumption process yields a value VI given by
for β ∈ [0,1]. The ex-ante utility U to the agent is the following,
Similarly to Epstein and Zin (1989), the utility function disentangles the relative risk aversion coefficient γ > 0, γ ≠ 1 from the elasticity of intertemporal substitution ψ > 0, ψ ≠ 1. As we will see, this choice is made to allows a better interpretations of the results. Notice also that by setting
C. The problem of the investor
At time t = 1, an investor first chooses whether to be active (τ = A) or passive (τ = P), then observes the corresponding signal Iτ, and finally makes investment decisions. Investment choices are given by a saving rate x and a portfolio share αm,j for every technology (m, j) in the economy, subject to the barrier to diversification
where,
Refinements (7) imply that for agents with an informative signal I = Θ uncertainty about the portfolio return
When I = 0 the signal is uninformative and, from the point of view of the investor, returns on all technologies are identically distributed. Therefore, to minimize risk, the investment is spread as evenly as possible across technologies, which implies that a share
Substituting for the optimal portfolio shares, we conclude that, for a given Θ, the portfolio return
Notice that
where
and
Risk adjusted returns are independent both on h and on the particular realization Θ. Since
Using the results obtained so far and the homotheticity of the utility function, the optimal saving rates are found by rewriting
For every signal I, the first order conditions of the problem give the optimal saving rate
Since all agents, informed or uninformed, allocate a fraction
For instance, when financial development is at its minimum
D. The microfundation of the information structure
When collection of information is costly markets cannot be informationally efficient (Grossman and Stiglitz [1980]), otherwise the superior information available to active investors would be costlessly revealed to passive investors by investment choices, which are publicly observable. However, if the precision of the public information is reduced by the presence of an aggregate noise, then costly collection of private information can still be valuable. This idea is formalized by assuming that passive investors observe the investments made by active investors plus a noise. The noise can be interpreted as created by mistakes in investment choices or in its measurement, or by the activity of another class of agents, the liquidity investors, whose portfolio decision is influenced by random factors, such as liquidity needs.
Assume that there is a constant amount
where as usual η is the fraction of investors active in each market. Each active investor has a net wealth 1/ξA and a saving rate
The value Lj corresponds to the realization of the noise L consistent with a observation y(m,j) and a realized type θm = j in our reference market m. For j = 1, 2 define Θ j ∈ TΘ the vector of types consistent with a realization θm = j in our reference market m. Appendix B shows that if (3) holds then,
where u(·) is the probability density function of L. First of all, notice that Prob{Θ1|y} + Prob{Θ2|y} = 1 and this is consistent with our initial assumption (4) that agents are always informed about
The externality function (8) is obtained by setting
E. Equilibrium
In an equilibrium where the revelation rate is strictly positive the fraction of active investors is also strictly positive. In this situation, the equilibrium revelation rate ρ* makes indifferent the marginal investor between being active or passive, that is
where the left hand side is the utility (9) from being active and the right hand side is the expected utility from being passive. Solving we obtain
An internal solution ρ* ∈ (0, 1) is obtained whenever
An equilibrium is given by
We have then the following Proposition.
Proof. Substitute (15) into (14) to obtain (18), which is then substituted into (17) to get (19). Q.E.D.
The equilibrium revelation rate is ultimately a function of the exogenous vector of distortions D, so we write ρ*(D). Since ρ* equalizes the value of being active and passive the revelation rate turns out to be, not surprisingly, a function of the relative information cost ξ and not of ξA and ξB separately. We can perform comparative statics exercises to see how financial innovation affects ρ* through reductions in the distortions D. In particular, to mimic the stylized facts suggested in Section II, I consider exogenous reductions in ξA, ξB and
Consider changes in D that leave ξ unchanged. Then,
If im = 1 a.s. then ρ*(D) is a strictly increasing function.
If em = 1 a.s. then ρ*(D) is strictly increasing for ψ < 1 and strictly decreasing for ψ > 1.
Welfare strictly decreases in the distorsions D.
Proposition 2 show that information collection decreases whenever financial innovation favors mostly passive investors relative to active investors. To explain this point it is useful to analyze the ratios ζx = xΘ/x0 and ζR = RΘ/Ro representing, respectively, the saving rate and risk adjusted return of an informed investor relative to those of an uninformed investor. In case i) informed investors face no risk at all since RΘ = 1, while passive investors face idiosyncratic and system risk. Financial development decreases the relative return ζR of informed investors by boosting only the return R0 of uninformed investors, who can better diversify the excess risk they hold. Since active investors are always informed while passive investors are sometimes uninformed, financial development favors passive investors relatively more than active investors. In case ii) we have ζR = Ω–1 where
The excess risk held by uninformed investors is all systemic, hence the relative return ζR is unaffected by the degree of diversification. In this case, therefore, the channel that allows D to affect ρ* is not simply the change in ζR, but is the behavior of the relative saving rate ζx. When the elasticity of intertemporal substitution is smaller than one ζx < 1, because the share of individual wealth consumed by informed investors, who face a higher return RΘ, is bigger than that of the uninformed investors, who save relatively more to compensate for their lower return R0. Therefore, even though financial innovation doesn’t change ζR, it still favors more uninformed investors (and thus passive investors) who are the ones that are more exposed to investment risk and then reap overall greater fruits from the improvement in diversification possibilities. The opposite i true when ψ > 1, but this latter case seems much less relevant for macroeconomics, where both the econometric (Hall [1988]) and the quantitative (Kydland and Prescott [1982]) literature traditionally consider values of ψ smaller than 0.5. For em = 1, the elasticity ψ determines the direction (decrease/increase) in which ρ* changes in response to a decrease in D, while the relative risk aversion γ influences the size of such change. In fact, substituting ζR = Ω–1 into (19) we obtain
where g(RΘ, Ω) is a strictly positive function. Risk adjusted returns increase with diversification4, so
Having established that financial innovation tends to decrease information, it is interesting to assess how this affects aggregate welfare and the business cycle. For equilibria with interior ρ*, investors’ welfare is simply given by the welfare of active investors
Lower public information means that more investors (lower η*) invest more often (lower ρ*) in the “wrong technologies”, i.e. in technologies with excess risk. This result is important and suggests that the finding of Proposition 1 regarding the positive welfare value of financial innovation could be quite fragile. Indeed, in Section IV I extend the basic framework to a more dynamic setting in which risk is time varying and where periods when excess risk is mainly idiosyncratic are followed by periods when excess risk becomes systemic. I show that financial development increases the probability of “liquidation crises”, i.e. situations in which investments in excess risk technologies, initially mistakenly undertaken by uninformed investors, are suddenly liquidated when the increase in systemic risk triggers a wave of information collection. If liquidation crises impose aggregate costs to the economy, then financial innovation can reduce welfare.
To present in simple ways the effect of financial innovation on the business cycle, I characterize the equilibrium values of the statistics
The multifactor productivity is the overall output at time 2 of the production technologies divided by time 1 total investment, and is expressed in (20) as the weighted average of the investors’ portfolio return divided by total investment. Define ∑2 the volatility of the excess risk technologies minus the volatility of i and S, and define
Appendix C shows that when total noise
Financial innovation, accompanied by a reduction in ρ*, has ambiguous effects on aggregate volatility
Clear-cut results are obtained for the sensitivity γA, S which always increases in
Figure 3 depicts, for a particular numerical example, how the probability density function of A and the revelation rate ρ* change with
Probability density function of A (left panel) and revelation rate (right panel) for minimum
Citation: IMF Working Papers 2010, 266; 10.5089/9781455210732.001.A001
The next section shows how systemic tail risk can be endogenously generated by financial innovation.
IV. Information cycles and liquidation crises
In this section I study the consequences of financial innovation in a multi-period model when the risk structure of the economy changes over time, creating endogenous information cycles and sudden liquidations of excess risk technologies. The main setup is similar to the one presented in the previous section, with three main differences. First, the economy lasts three periods t = 1, 2, 3 and information and investment choices are made both at the beginning of time 1 and of time 2. Second, the structure of excess risk is time varying, since it is all idiosyncratic at time 1 and all systemic at time 2. Third, the systemic shock at time 2 is partly endogenous, since it depends on the possibility of a “liquidation crisis”. Liquidation shocks take the form of a reduction δ in the time 2 returns of all technologies and occurs if, at the beginning of time 2, public information reveals the types to previously uninformed investors, thus triggering a wave of liquidations of their investments in excess risk technologies. The aggregate liquidation cost δ can be interpreted, for instance, as capital adjustment costs arising from the liquidation and reinvestment of capital from excess risk technologies to low risk technologies. Alternatively, δ could be the productivity costs of a banking crisis, triggered by financial intermediaries losses in the liquidation of excess risk technologies, similarly to Diamond and Rajan (2009) and Diamond (1991). The probability of a liquidation crisis is endogenous, since it depends on the public information revelation rates, which are ultimately related to the vector of distortions D. Under quite general assumptions I will show that, absent a reduction in the relative cost of information, financial innovation decreases welfare because it increases the probability of liquidation crises. The reason is that financial development creates incentives to collect less information during times when excess risk is idiosyncratic, but does not affect information collection during periods when excess risk is systemic. In the terms of the model, lower distortions D decrease the revelation rate at time 1, but does not change the revelation rate at time 2. Consequently, the probability that at time 1 the economy undertakes investments in excess risk technologies increases, and thus the probability of a liquidation crisis at time 2 raises. Much of the basic structure of the problem is based on the simple two period model in Section 3. The timeline is sketched in Figure IV. At the beginning of time 1, agents draw a specialization h and a type Θ is realized; depending on their choice τ1 = A, P, agents pay the cost
The extended model with time varying risk: sequence of actions.
Citation: IMF Working Papers 2010, 266; 10.5089/9781455210732.001.A001
I consider the analytically simplest extension of (9) to the three period case by assuming that the utility function has the following logarithmic7 form
where, for t = 1, 2
For t = 1, 2 call rm,j,t the return technology (m, j) between time t and t + 1. Assume that
The support of S1 is the set binary {0,1} and Prob{S1 = 1} = πs. Shocks S2 and em are i.i.d., have mean equal to 1, satisfy em, S2 ≠ 1 almost surely and are independent on S1 and on
Equation (28) implies that a necessary condition for the occurrence of a liquidation crisis at time 2 is that public information at time 1 is not revealing
where ρt are the revelation rates at time t associated with two mutually independent9 shocks
The return
Corresponding to the unadjusted returns
for all h.
with
therefore
If
V. Conclusions
The empirical evidence suggests that financial innovation increases diversification opportunities and reduces investment costs, but does not reduce the relative cost of information. I construct an analytically tractable theoretical model that examines how financial innovation affects incentives to collect costly information about the riskiness of production technologies. I find that financial innovation tends to be associated with lower collection of private information and thus, via a spillover effect, with lower quality of public information. This result has important implications for the business cycle, since aggregate productivity becomes more subject to systemic shocks, even when its overall volatility decreases. Recent empirical evidence shows that in the US agents have indeed shifted over time from active to passive investment strategies. Higher diversification and lower investment costs improve welfare, even though the lower quality of information has a negative effects on passive investors. In an extended model where risk is time varying risk, financial innovation increases the probability of liquidity crises. In fact, financial innovation lowers information collection during periods in which excess risk is mainly idiosyncratic and thus increases the frequency at which uninformed agents mistakenly invest in excess risk technologies. Liquidity crises arise when the excess risk becomes systemic: information collection rises and triggers a wave of liquidation. If liquidation crises impose aggregate costs to the economy then financial innovation can decrease welfare. The paper shows that financial innovation and endogenous information collection can be intertwined in important ways. More research on this issue is certainly needed.
References
Azariadis C., Kass L. (2003), Endogenous financial development, growth and volatility, University of Vienna mimeo.
Bank for International Settlements (2008), Private equity and leveraged finance markets, CGFS Paper n. 30.
Benmelech E., Kandel E., Veronesi P., (2009), Stock-Based Compensation and CEO (Dis)Incentives, mimeo.
Cremers M. K. J., Petajisto A., (2009), How Active Is Your Fund Manager? A New Measure That Predicts Performance, The Review of Financial Studies 22, 3329-3365.
Diamond D.W., (1991), Debt Maturity Structure and Liquidity Risk, The Quarterly Journal of Economics 106, 709-737.
Diamond D.W., Rajan R., (2009), Fear of fire sales and the credit freeze, mimeo.
Dynan K. E., Elmendorf D.W., Sichel D.E., (2006) Can financial innovation help to explain the reduced volatility of economic activity?, Journal of Monetary Economics 53, 123-150.
Epstein L.G., Zin S.E., (1989), Substitution, Risk Aversion, and the Temporal Behavior of Consumption Growth and Asset Returns I: A Theoretical Framework, Econometrica 57, 937-969.
Fogli A., Perrri F., (2006), The Great Moderation and the U.S. External Imbalance, Monetary and Economic Studies 24, 209-225.
French K.R., (2008), The cost of active trading, The Journal of Finance 63, 1537 - 1573.
Gorton G., (2008), The Subprime Panic, NBER Working Paper No. 14398.
Grossman S.J., Stiglitz J.E., (1980), On the Impossibility of Informationally Efficient Markets, The American Economic Review 70, 393-408.
Hall R. E., (1988), Intertemporal substitution in consumption, Journal of Political Economy 96, 339-357.
Holmström B., Milgrom P., (1987), Aggregation and Linearity in the Provision of Intertemporal Incentives, Econometrica 55, 303328.
Jones C.M., (2002), A century of stock market liquidity and trading costs, mimeo, Columbia University.
Kaplan S. N., Strömberg P., (2009), Leveraged buyouts and private equity, Journal of Economic Perspectives 23, 121-46.
Kydland F.E., Prescott E.C. (1982), Time to Build and Aggregate Fluctuations, Econometrica 50, 1345-1370.
Kyle A.S., (1985), Continuous Auctions and Insider Trading, Econometrica 53, 1315-1335.
Levine R., (1997), Financial development and economic growth: views and agenda, Journal of Economic Literature 35, 688-726.
Mendoza E., Quadrini V., Ríos-Rull V., (2008), Financial integration, financial development and global imbalances, mimeo.
Merton R. C., (1987), A Simple Model of Capital Market Equilibrium with Incomplete Information, The Journal of Finance 42, 483-509.
Rajan R., Zingales L., (1998), Financial dependence and growth, American Economic Review 88, 559-586.
Rajan R., (2005), Has financial development made the world riskier?, NBER Working Paper No. 11728.
Shin H.S., (2009), Financial intermediation and the post-crisis financial system, presented at the 8th BIS Annual Conference.
Stiroh K.J., (2009), Volatility accounting: a production perspective on increased economic stability, Journal of the European Economic Association 7, 671-696.
Stock J., Watson M.W., (2002), Has the Business Cycle Changed and Why?, NBER Working Paper No. 9127.
Townsend R., (1979). Optimal contracts and competitive markets with costly state verification, Journal of Economic Theory 21, 265-293.
Tufano (2002), Handbook of Financial Economics.
Van Nieuwerburgh S., Veldkamp L., (2008), Information Acquisition and Under-Diversification NBER Working Papers 13904.
Weaver K. (2008), US asset-backed securities market review and outlook, mimeo, Deutsche Bank.
APPENDIX A
I find the optimal portfolio shares
Step 1) Assume I = 0. From the point of view of a passive investors, all technologies have identically distributed returns. The return on technology (j, m) can then be written as
Notice that
I show that any choice of portfolio shares
Define
Notice that
Since im and em are i.i.d. across m we have
Therefore,
and then
qv is a mean preserving spread of
Step 2) Assume I = 0. I show that the portfolio
Similarly to Step 1 define qα and z as
Since qα is independent of Ө it follows that
and then again E [z|qα] = 0. Since
Step 3) Assume I = Ө. I show that any choice of portfolio shares
Define qv, qα as usual as the returns of portfolios ν and α, and define z as
Since em and S are independent from qα, then E [z |qα = 0]. The portfolio qν = qα + z is a mean preserving spread of qα.
Step 4) Assume I ∈ {Ө, 0}. For any
where rm is the average return in market m obtained by averaging the contribution of each technologies j = 1, 2 using weights
It is easy to show that
Conditional on any value of α(1/N), Jensen’s inequality gives
This proves that as
APPENDIX B
In this appendix I present the signal extraction problem of passive investors. Choose any market m. For j = 1, 2 define
The realization of the noise L satisfies L ∈ {L1, L2}. Hence, for every every market m′ and j′ = 1, 2 it must be the case that
In this way, we associate to each realization L = Lj one and only one vector of types. More precisely, for a realization ŷ, call Өj the unique vector of types associated with the event {L = Lj} ∩ {y = ŷ}. Notice that the true type Ө satisfies
where θm is type true realization in our reference market m. Notice also that
Using Bayes rule (for continuous variables) and the arguments above we have
where u is the probability density function of L. Using (3) and (A33) we conclude that
APPENDIX C
This appendix computes the business cycle statistics and establishes the monotonicity of
Conditional on an informative signal IP = Ө all the agents invest in the low risk technologies, thus the productivity A is
If IP = 0 passive investors split equally their portfolio between the low risk and excess risk technologies and then
Recalling that η* = ρ*/AE we derive the unconditional covariance Cov(A, S) as
The unconditional variance is
For the dispersion
Therefore,
The above equation established that the variance
Since
APPENDIX D
Here I provide the solution to the extended model. The revelation rates ρt are solved by backward induction. Conditional on
The first order condition gives x* = β which implies
The revelation rate
Recall that, conditional on
The optimal investment is again x = β. The solution is
The revelation rate
APPENDIX E
This appendix provides details for the construction of the series in Figure 1. All data are taken from the Tables in French (2008). Starting from the top panel, the active and passive costs for DB plans are reported in Table III. For the bottom panel, the cost of the composite passive strategy is given in Table VII, column “Total Cost”. I construct the composite active strategy as a weighted average of investments in mutual funds, pension funds and hedge funds. The weight for the mutual funds is constructed using the market share for Open-end funds in Table I. This probably slightly overestimates by how much this component has decreased, since mutual funds has shifted overtime towards passive strategies, which are less costly. Nonetheless in 2006 as much as 88% of the Open-end funds are defined as active (Table II). The weight of the pension funds is constructed summing the shares of DB plans and DC plans in Table I. The weight for hedge funds is constructed using the share in Table I. The cost of Open-end funds is given in Table II, column “Total”. The costs of pension funds is the cost of active DB plans in Table III. The cost of the hedge funds is the one reported in Table IV under “Hedge Fund plus Fund of Funds”; I fill the missing values for dates prior to 1996 by using 9.27%, which is the 1996 value. This has no significant impact on the estimation of the cost index, since hedge funds have weights smaller than 2.3% for the years prior to 1996.
I would like to thank participants and discussants to seminars at the Bank of Italy, the BIS, the Society for Economic Dynamics 2010 and the Midwest Macro Conference 2010. In particular, I have greatly benefited from discussions with Fabrizio Perri, Timothy Kehoe, Patrick Kehoe and Jean-Charles Rochet. Any remaining errors are the authors’ responsibility.
* I would like to thank Fabrizio Perri, Timothy Kehoe, Patrick Kehoe and two anonymous referees for useful comments. The initial draft of this paper was written while at the Bank of Italy. The views expressed here are those of the author and not necessarily those of the International Monetary Fund or of the Bank of Italy. Contact information: tel.: (+001) 202 623 4825; e-mail: rpiazza@imf.org.
To reduce notation, I normalize to zero the amount of systemic risk in the diversifiable technology technologies. This has no qualitative effect on the results. A case with systemic risk also in the low risk technology is presented in Section IV.
This gives rise to a constant return to scale for information collection. For a analysis of increasing returns technologies see Van Nieuwerburgh and Veldkamp (2008).
For a detailed derivation see Appendix A
Appendix A proves this point formally.
If
See Appendix C.
The qualitative results presented do not depend on the logarithmic form. The full extension of utility (9) to a multiperiod case can be done using Epstein and Zin (1989) recursive preference. This more general setting is available upon request from the author.
There is no learning when S1 = 0, since technologies have identical return at time 1.
This is the case if liquidity noises Lt for t = 1; 2 are independent of each other.